• Open access
  • Published: 22 October 2021

Integrating patient management, reflective practice, and ethical decision-making in an emergency medicine intern boot camp

  • Serpil Yaylaci   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0001-9950-4118 1 ,
  • Yesim Isil Ulman   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0001-5601-1508 2 ,
  • Kevser Vatansever   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-8943-9874 3 ,
  • Gamze Senyurek   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-8127-1827 4 ,
  • Suha Turkmen   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-8010-4453 1 ,
  • Hasan Aldinc   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-4734-5319 1 &
  • Cem Gun   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0001-5907-5056 1  

BMC Medical Education volume  21 , Article number:  536 ( 2021 ) Cite this article

2656 Accesses

4 Citations

1 Altmetric

Metrics details

Integration of clinical skills, ethical decision-making, and reflection skills have emerged as cornerstones of clinical teaching in medical schools. This study aimed to detect whether a multimodal learning environment approach consisting of lectures, a drill, post-drill video debriefing, and written reflection in an emergency medicine rotation boot camp improves interns’ patient management skills, ethical decision-making, and reflection skills.

A multimodal learning environment was created by the collaboration of emergency medicine, ethics, and medical education specialists. Multiple educational techniques involving lectures, case discussions, and role-playing a crisis scenario were applied. Pre-test and post-test, debriefing on performances on video records, video-recorded performance assessment, and reflective essays about their own and group’s performances were used to assess various aspects of the student performances. Additionally, a meeting was organized with the presence of the authors to create qualitative data obtained through the program evaluation meeting conducted on three themes: influences of teaching methods, students’ performances, and common achievements and mistakes of students.

133 students participated. Post-test multiple-choice question (MCQ) test scores were slightly higher than pre-test. A low and medium correlation was detected among pre-test and post-test patient management problem (PMP) and reflection scores, which was more prominent for female students. Multiple linear regression showed that pre-test and post-test PMP scores significantly contributed to reflection scores. These results might support that better patient management predicts more robust reflective practice. Teachers observed that students appreciated being inspired by well-performing peers, particularly noting the empathic needs of patients, companions, and other health professionals. However, students overlooked summoning forensic or social services and were inhibited by the pressure of the contextual traits of the drill.

The multimodal learning environment created by multidisciplinary collaboration contributed to the improvement of components of situational awareness of the interns: patient management skills, ethical decision-making, and reflective practice. During this research, we created a toolbox better to capture the richness and diversity of student interactions. Considering the scarcity of context-specific assessment methods and widespread use of MCQs or generic scales for higher-order thinking skills in medicine, this study might be regarded as a step forward in that context.

Peer Review reports

Introduction

Emergency medicine operates against time pressures in the care of patients in life-threatening situations and entails numerous ethical dilemmas. Although fundamental ethical obligations such as informed consent and confidentiality might sometimes not be fully met for patients in emergency care, respect for patient autonomy, beneficence, nonmaleficence, privacy and confidentiality, and fairness must be balanced with optimal care [ 1 , 2 ] in line with sound ethical decision-making.

Reflection is an important step in ethical reasoning and decision-making and involves the following steps: analyzing the underlying dilemma, realizing duties and responsibilities in terms of conflicting values, presenting a solution in the light of ethical principles, and decision testing [ 3 , 4 ]. Strategies to enhance the learning of clinical reasoning include both internally focused reflection and external reflective verbal or written articulation [ 5 ]. In medical education, reflection mostly occurs after the event (reflection-on-action). Written exercises, or recently digital records, are suggested as guided writing of reflection on the action and are advantageous because of the use of a structured design that is a critical aspect for enhancing reflection [ 5 , 6 ].

Tsai and Harasym noted the importance of considering medical indications, quality of life, the patient’s preferences, and the current context in ethical reasoning [ 7 ]. This results in transformative learning, which was described by Mezirow as self-reviewing in the presence of a disorienting dilemma, performing the premise reflection, recognizing the change in others, formulation of an action plan, acquisition of the knowledge and skills required to execute the plan, competency, and self-confidence improvement for new roles, and re-adaptation to life with new perspectives [ 8 ]. Effective reflection requires time, effort, willingness to question actions, beliefs, values, and to search for other viewpoints. This approach moves beyond the single loop of solely seeking an alternative plan or the double loop to find out the reasons for the outcome, and proceeds to a triple loop of transformation that necessitates questioning the underlying conceptual frameworks [ 6 ]. The most important point is to provide students with the opportunities to reflect and reveal their deepest thoughts and views in the presence of a role model in a safe, simulated environment [ 9 , 10 ].

Debriefing is a purposeful, structured reflection technique that involves reflecting on the experienced event, discussing experiences with others, and learning and modifying behaviors [ 10 ]. Evaluation of reflection is essential since it motivates learning and especially shared reflection is better than individual and self-assessment [ 6 ]. Reflective writing is also reported to produce a profound improvement in students’ professional affective skills [ 11 ], and rubric scales are proposed as an appropriate method for analyzing the level of reflection [ 12 ].

In the last decades, integration of clinical skills, ethical decision-making, and reflection skills have emerged as cornerstones of clinical teaching in medical schools, but all are seldom linked in curricula [ 13 ]. The innovative program of Brunger et al. [ 13 ] in the first year of Faculty of Medicine of Memorial University that aimed to integrate critical self-reflection, reflection on the political, economic, and cultural contexts shaping health and health care, and moral decision-making, could be looked into as one of the few examples in medical education. As well as medical education, there are several studies in health professionals education, i.e. nursing and physical therapy, discussing the integration of clinical reasoning with ethical reasoning or with reflection [ 14 , 15 , 16 , 17 , 18 , 19 ]. However, there seems to be a gap in the literature on health professionals’ education related to the teaching of clinical reasoning/decision-making, reflection, and ethical reasoning/decision-making in a manner that integrates all three aspects.

It was noticed that in the literature, assessment of ethics skills was solely based on pre- post-tests, multiple-choice questions (MCQs), or generic test batteries such as Defining Issues Test or Moral Judgment Tests [ 20 , 21 , 22 , 23 , 24 ]. Additionally, there are also studies reporting the use of performance tests with virtual or standardized patients [ 25 , 26 , 27 ].

At the Acibadem Mehmet Ali Aydinlar University School of Medicine (SoM), medical ethics, bioethics, and professionalism are integrated into the curriculum longitudinally in phase one (years 1–3). In phase 2, (years 4–5) “Ethics Rounds” are practiced within the clinical clerkships [ 28 ]. The aim of these is to integrate previously learned ethical issues into clinical training [ 29 , 30 ]. In phase 3 (year 6), integration of both clinical and ethical decision-making with reflection skills constitutes an example of a spiral and vertically integrated program for teaching those higher-order thinking skills, which are crucial for the nurturing of virtuous physicians [ 31 ].

During the emergency medicine internship in phase 3, a novel module has been implemented to blend clinical reasoning, ethical decision-making, and reflection in an emergency care drill during the rotation before emergency department attachment. The novel module was included in the abdominal pain day of a 5-day long boot camp that focused on diagnosing and managing different life-threatening situations. Each day, situations such as altered mental status, chest pain and dyspnea, multiple traumas, and a busy emergency department were taught. In addition, high-fidelity simulators were utilized, the faculty and intern doctors were included in role-playing scenarios, and the interns were given a chance for reflection throughout [ 32 ]. The learning outcomes of this boot camp were improving difficult situation management, reflection and communication skills, and patient management in an integrated, interactive, feedback-given environment.

This study aimed to examine the relationships between patient management skills, ethical decision-making, and reflective practice to introduce the multimodal learning environment designed for interns at the Acibadem Mehmet Ali Aydinlar University SoM to improve clinical management, ethical reasoning, and reflection skills. The environment was introduced in the five-day-long boot camp of the emergency medicine rotation. Lastly, it was aimed to present the study results obtained through the quantitative assessment methods and the qualitative data obtained through a program evaluation meeting.

This study was approved by the Acibadem Mehmet Ali Aydinlar University Research Ethics Committee (ATADEK) with the decision number: 2018–2/68. The written informed consent was obtained from the participants before the practice. All methods were performed in accordance with the relevant guidelines and regulations.

Technical information

In an emergency medicine rotation intern boot camp, does a multimodal learning environment approach consisting of lectures, a drill, post-drill video debriefing, and written reflection improve the patient management skills, ethical decision-making, and reflective practice of interns?

Study design

A multimodal learning environment was created by the multidisciplinary collaboration of emergency medicine, ethics, and medical education specialists. This study was created as a multi-method design consisting of quantitative student assessment methods, and also presents the qualitative data obtained through the program evaluation meeting conducted with the presence of the authors SY, YIU, GS, KV.

Multiple educational techniques involving lectures, case discussions, and role-playing a crisis scenario were applied. Pre-test and post-test, debriefing on performances on video records, video-recorded performance assessment (VPA), and reflective essays about their own and group’s performances were used for the assessment of various aspects of the student performances. Additionally, a meeting was organized with the presence of the authors SY, YIU, KV, and GS to evaluate the program. During the meeting, observations, and opinions of authors as teachers were obtained on three themes: (1) influences of teaching methods, (2) students’ performances, and (3) common achievements and mistakes of students.

The study group consisted of interns from the Acibadem Mehmet Ali Aydinlar University SoM in their emergency medicine rotations. The research was conducted over two years (2018–2019) with eight consecutive groups undergoing “Abdominal Pain Day” of the five-day-long boot camps before the beginning of the emergency medicine rotation (Table  1 ).

Learning outcomes

The program aimed to assist the interns in preparation for clinical and ethical decision-making in their prospective professional lives. Targeted learning outcomes include:

Applying basic principles of clinical management of life-threatening conditions

Acknowledging the rules and principles of ethics in emergency health care services

Practicing informed consent with emergency patients

Articulating the main attributes of ethical decision-making

Analyzing the components of difficult situation management

Experimenting with empathic, effective, and participative communication with patients and companions

The interns were given a one-hour lecture and a discussion session on the management of abdominal pain in the emergency department. Following this, a pre-test was administered. The goals and expectations concerning the drill were explained and the students were asked to select opposite gender roles during role-playing to experience empathy with the opposite gender.

A post-test that was identical to the pre-test was applied. Seven MCQs for assessing remembering and comprehending and three patient management problems (PMPs) for assessing the cognitive skills of applying and analyzing were used (Additional file 1 ). After the post-test, in a video debriefing session, students evaluated and reflected on the role-play, discussed their own experiences, and described what had been learned and what else was needed for better performance. Assessment tools consisted of rubric forms; one was used for students’ reflective essays and the other was used for VPA. The reflective essays were also used as a tool for self-directed learning by reviewing these with students on the third week of the rotation and by asking them to assess their progress and their plans to improve further.

As for qualitative data, observations and opinions of the authors SY, YIU, KV, and GS that were obtained in the program evaluation meeting were presented. The meeting was focused on the observations and opinions on (1) evaluating the influences of teaching content and methods, (2) students’ performances, and (3) common achievements, mistakes, and stereotypes of the interns. Meeting notes were discussed in the presence of all and decided to be reported in this manuscript as qualitative data.

The drill scenario consisted of five roles: physician, nurse, patient, the patient’s mother, and the patient’s brother. These were designed according to a hidden curriculum aspect consisting of one adult and one minor patient, both of whom were hemodynamically unstable due to a rupture of ectopic pregnancy as a result of an extramarital relationship. All roles were played by the interns. The video recording was then watched with the interns, and a debriefing was given. The drill was concluded with the reflective essays from the interns.

The footage recorded during the drill was assessed by two teachers (one ethicist and one emergency medicine physician) and was scored in line with the VPA rubric form. If the scores of two teachers were inconsistent, they negotiated and settled on an agreed score. The group performance results were adopted as the individual interns’ VPA scores. The VPA topics on the rubric form are presented in Tables 2 and 3 below:

Statistical analysis

Descriptive statistics were presented using mean, standard deviation, median, minimum, maximum. Paired Samples t-test was used to compare two normally distributed dependent groups.

Spearman’s rho correlation analysis was used to analyze relationships between two non-normally distributed variables. Multiple linear regression analysis was used to predict interns’ reflective essay scores. The data categories from 133 interns were as follows: reflective essay scores, gender, VPA scores, pre-test and post-test MCQs and PMPs. The backward variable selection method was used.

Statistical significance was accepted when two-sided p values were lower than 0.05.

Statistical analysis was performed using MedCalc Statistical Software version 12.7.7.

The research sample consisted of all 133 interns of the Acibadem Mehmet Ali Aydinlar University SoM attending emergency medicine internship in eight groups consisting of 12–21 students (Mean: 16.63). Seventy-seven (57.9%) students were women and 56 (42.1%) were men. Students’ mean age was 24.1  ±  1.26 years (Median: 24; Interquartile Range: 22–31).

Table  4 shows the average scores of students for all assessment methods. Detailed research data is available in Additional file  2 .

The total post-test MCQ score was slightly higher than the pre-test MCQs (p: 0.010). The difference in the post-test PMPs was not found to have a statistically significant difference with the pre-test PMPs. The mean VPA scores were 28.86 out of 40, the mean reflective writing score was 18.76 out of 30, and the mean total post-test score was 63.40 out of 86.

Correlation coefficients of total and all reflection questions’ scores, and VPA scores with pre-test and post-test MCQ and PMP are presented in Table  5 .

VPA Video-recorded Performance Assessment, MCQ Multiple-Choice Questions, PMP Patient Management Problems) Spearman’s rho,p * < 0.05, ** < 0.001.

Total scores of pre-test and post-test MCQ were found to be moderately correlated (0.46). Pre-test and post-test PMP scores were also found to have a moderate correlation (0.404). A weak correlation between pre-test MCQ and VPA was detected (0.272). For female students, post-test MCQ scores showed a moderate correlation with VPA scores (0.399). Reflection essay scores had no correlation with the pre-test and post-test MCQs, except low correlation of reflection question 6 for male students (0.345). There was a weak correlation of all reflection essay questions and total scores with pre-test PMP and post-test PMP scores, changing from 0.182 to 0.279 (Table 5 ). This correlation was more prominent among female interns for pre-test PMP scores, changing from 0.253 to 0.357.

The multiple linear regression to predict reflection scores from gender, pre-test, and post-test MCQ, PMP, and VPA scores are presented in Table  6 .

The backward variable selection method was used. No autocorrelation (Durbin Watson value = 1.808 < 2) or multicollinearity (VIF = 1.082 < 10) were present. The model was found to be significant (F = 7039, p  = 0.001). Pre-test and post-test PMP scores significantly contributed to the prediction of reflection scores ( p  < 0.05) with one unit change in the pre-test PMP increasing the reflection score 0.538 points and one unit of change in the post-test PMP increasing the reflection score 0.404 points. The equation for predicting reflection scores from pre-test and post-test PMPs was =12.039 + 0.538 (pre-test PMP score) + 0.559 (post-test PMP score).

Opinions and observations of teachers obtained in the program evaluation meeting revealed that the boot camp had increased both the performance and enthusiasm of the students in the following seven-week rotation. Also, the scenario had worked well, and students made genuine efforts to find solutions. In the video debriefing sessions, students appreciated the opportunity of peer learning through inspiration from good performances of role model peers. Students’ approaches were those of novices, and the contextual features of the case had affected the decision-making process and the intervention. Likewise, interns established less contact with forensic or social services than expected. While role-playing, students mostly portrayed the conservative brother as a man of low socioeconomic status. This highlights an important clue to a student prejudice, that conservative men are of low socioeconomic status. Another noteworthy observation was that female students exhibited a more patient and genuine approach toward an interfering companion. It was remarkable that students frequently emphasized that they had learned the empathy needs of the patient, companions, and other team members.

This study describes a one-day drill program using multiple methods of teaching and assessment and aiming to teach clinical decision-making, ethical decision-making, and reflection skills in medical emergency cases, in an integrated approach.

There are several studies in medical education and health professionals’ education literature that integrate either clinical reasoning/decision-making with ethical reasoning/decision-making or reflection skills [ 13 , 14 , 15 , 16 , 17 , 18 , 19 ]. Thus, the current study seems to be an innovative example for integrating the teaching of clinical reasoning/decision-making, reflection, and ethical reasoning/decision-making.

Despite the fact that integration of clinical skills, ethical decision-making, and reflection skills have emerged as cornerstones of clinical teaching in medical schools recently [ 13 ], assessment methods seem to be limited to MCQs in some studies or generic test batteries for ethics [ 20 , 21 , 22 , 23 , 24 ], which put forward the current study in terms of assessing all learning domains integrated. Verbal or written articulation of reflection for assessing reflection skills and rubric scales for analyzing the level of reflection is proposed as appropriate methods [ 12 ]. The REFLECT rubric including the levels of Non-reflective: Habitual Action, Non-reflective: Thoughtful Action, Reflective, and Critically Reflective developed by Wald et al. [ 12 ] are quite similar to the model employed by the current study’s design.

In this study, a slight but statistically significant difference was detected between pre-test and post-test MCQ scores. In the literature, there are studies on ethics education in medical schools reporting no statistically significant difference [ 20 ] or significant increase in post-test scores [ 21 ].

The correlation of pre-test and post-test PMP scores with reflection essay scores implied that when students acquire higher levels of cognitive skills, i.e., applying and analyzing, they might perform better in terms of higher-order thinking skills such as reflection. Moreover, the multiple linear regression results support this finding and show that the pre-test and post-test PMP scores contribute significantly to the prediction of reflection scores. These results might support that, better patient management predicts more robust reflective practice.

The spiral model of ethics education in the Acibadem Mehmet Ali Aydinlar University SoM which starts from the first year and introduces more advanced applications or new skills related to those previously covered in the previous years might have contributed to this result. The effect of the contextual features of the case on students’ decision-making and intervention pointed out the need for greater opportunity to work independently and to encounter more complex cases in the previous clinical education. Observing students’ prejudice towards the patient’s brother evoked the need for structured skills training regarding difficult situation management. Besides, fewer students contacted with forensic or social services than expected implied the need to emphasize more when and how to involve forensic and social services in difficult situations.

During this research, we created a toolbox to better capture the richness and diversity of student interactions. A transformative loop, capable of triggering a transformation in self-confidence, supporting the questioning of assumptions, and experiences giving the opportunity to reflect on the actions in both the teachers and the students was formed in the integrated, effective, and supportive learning environment. Students’ situational awareness was improved, and both parties had a view of the traits in the hidden curriculum, such as pre-acceptance of conservative men belonging to low socioeconomic status.

The scarcity of context-specific assessment methods and widespread use of MCQs or generic scales for ethical reasoning in the literature revealed the need for implementing innovative and multi-method assessing ethical reasoning, clinical judgment, and reflection skills in difficult situations [ 33 ]. The present study might be regarded as a step forward in that context. Consequently, instead of solely relying on didactic classroom lectures or video demonstration, other environments described in this paper, which enable the students to experience in a kinesthetic fashion, and to reflect on actions of themselves and their groups, could be beneficial. It is thought that similar programs might be of assistance in producing virtuous physicians [ 31 ] who also act as moral agents in health care provision.

Future studies in which students reflect on their performances and the use of these writings for following up on their progress might be conducted to assess their reflection skills and self-directed learning.

Limitations

Students’ reflection essays were not used for following up on their improvement throughout the rotation or the year. No written or structured oral feedback was obtained from the students. Structured qualitative data was not collected.

Conclusions

This study describes a novel and innovative program utilizing multiple teaching and assessment methods to teach and assess the interrelation between clinical decision-making, ethical decision-making, and reflection with an integrated approach.

Lectures helped students to retrieve previous learning and provided a focus for ethical dilemmas in medical emergency cases. Role-playing the opposite gender and acting as a patient and interfering companion helped the interns to see the gaps in their empathic behaviors and provided a framework for improvement in handling a disorienting dilemma. Debriefing sessions and reflection essays gave them the opportunity for premise reflection, by asking them to reflect on their feelings, thoughts, performances, and their own and peers’ weaknesses or strengths. Reflection essays supplied them with the clues for self-directing their learning and improving their clinical and ethical decision-making skills by formulating action plans to learn further.

Availability of data and materials

All data generated or analyzed during this study are included in this published article and its supplementary information files.

Sanders AB. Emergency  and trauma medicine ethics. In: Singer PA, Viens AM, editors. The Cambridge textbook of bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2008. p. 469–74.

American College of Emergency Physicians. Code of Ethics for Emergency Physicians. 2017:6–8. https://www.acep.org/globalassets/new-pdfs/policy-statements/code-of-ethics-for-emergency-physicians.pdf . Accessed 15 Oct 2021.

Mamede S, Schmidt HG. The structure of reflective practice in medicine. Med Educ. 2004;38(12):1302–8.

Article   Google Scholar  

Zhang LF. The Perry scheme: across cultures, across approaches to the study of human psychology. J Adult Dev. 2004;11:123–38.

Atkinson HL, Nixon-Cave K. A tool for clinical reasoning and reflection using the international classification ofFunctioning, disability and health (ICF) framework and patient management model. Phys Ther. 2011;91:426–30.

Aronson L. Twelve tips for teaching reflection at all levels of medical education. Med Teach. 2011;33:200–5.

Tsai TC, Harasym PH. A medical ethical reasoning model and its contributions to medical education. Med Educ. 2010;44:864–73.

Mezirow J. How critical reflection triggers transformative learning. In: Mezirow J, et al., editors. Fostering critical reflection in adulthood: a guide to transformative and emancipatory learning. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass Publishers; 1990. p. 1–20.

Google Scholar  

Vatansever K. Tıpta etik ve entelektuel gelisme ve biyoetik egitimi. In: Bioethics in a Changing World, edited by YI Ulman and F Artvinli, published by the Turkish Bioethics Association, No: XVIII, Istanbul, Turkey, ISBN: 978–975-7041-15-3 2012: 51–65. https://www.acibadem.edu.tr/doc/Degisen_Dunyada_Biyoetik.pdf . Accessed 15 Oct 2021.

Husebø SE, O’Regan S, Nestel D. Reflective practice and its role in simulation. Clin Simul Nurs. 2015;11:368–75.

Dhaliwal U, Singh S, Singh N. Reflective student narratives: honing professionalism and empathy. Indian J Med Ethics. 2018;3:9–15.

Wald HS, Borkan JM, Taylor JS, Anthony D, Reis SP. Fostering and evaluating reflective capacity in medical education: developing the REFLECT rubric for assessing reflective writing [published correction appears in Acad med. 2012 mar;87(3):355]. Acad Med. 2012;87:41–50.

Brunger F, Duke PS. The evolution of integration: innovations in clinical skills and ethics in first year medicine. Med Teach. 2012;34:e452–8.

Murphy JI. Using focused reflection and articulation to promote clinical reasoning: an evidence-based teaching strategy. Nurs Educ Perspect. 2004;25:226–31.

Kaldjian LC. Teaching practical wisdom in medicine through clinical judgement, goals of care, and ethical reasoning. J Med Ethics. 2010;36:558–62.

Russell BH, Geist MJ, Maffett JH. SAFETY: an integrated clinical reasoning and reflection framework for undergraduate nursing students. J Nurs Educ. 2013;52:59–62.

Mosalanejad L, Ebrahimi AM, Tafvizi M, Zarifsanaiey N. A constructive blended approach to ethical reasoning: the impact on medical students’ reflection and learning. Shiraz E Med J. 2020;21:1–8.

Salminen H, Zary N, Björklund K, Toth-Pall E, Leanderson C. Virtual patients in primary care: developing a reusable model that fosters reflective practice and clinical reasoning. J Med Internet Res. 2014;16:e3.

Edwards I, Braunack-Mayer A, Jones M. Ethical reasoning as a clinical-reasoning strategy in physiotherapy. Physiotherapy. 2005;91:229–36.

Angelos P, DaRosa DA, Derossis AM, Kim B. Medical ethics curriculum for surgical residents: results of a pilot project. Surgery. 1999;126:701–7.

Beigy M, Pishgahi G, Moghaddas F, et al. Students' medical ethics rounds: a combinatorial program for medical ethics education. J Med Ethics Hist Med. 2016;9:3.

Murrell VS. The failure of medical education to develop moral reasoning in medical students. Int J Med Educ. 2014;5:219–25.

Carrese JA, Malek J, Watson K, et al. The essential role of medical ethics education in achieving professionalism: the Romanell report. Acad Med. 2015;90:744–52.

Al-Jalahma M, Fakhroo E. Teaching medical ethics: implementation and evaluation of a new course during residency training in Bahrain. Educ Health (Abingdon). 2004;17:62–72.

Hooper CR, Jivram T, Law S, Michell A, Somasunderam A. Using virtual patients to teach medical ethics, medical law and medical professionalism. Med Teach. 2012;34:674–5.

Smith SR, Balint JA, Krause KC, Moore-West M, Viles PH. Performance-based assessment of moral reasoning and ethical judgment among medical students. Acad Med. 1994;69:381–6.

Buxton M, Phillippi JC, Collins MR. Simulation: a new approach to teaching ethics. J Midwifery Womens Health. 2015;60:70–4.

Ulman YI, Topsever P, Vatansever K, et al. Ethical reasoning in clinical years: Ethics rounds, Acibadem university experience. Paper presented at: 28th European Conference on Philosophy of Medicine and Health Care; Debrecen, Hungary, 27–30 August 2014; p. 78–9. https://www.espmh.org/wp-content/uploads/Abstract-booklet-Debrecen-2014-10-July.pdf . Accessed 15 Oct 2021.

Fryer-Edwards K, Wilkins MD, Baernstein A, Braddock CH 3rd. Bringing ethics education to the clinical years: ward ethics sessions at the University of Washington. Acad Med. 2006;81:626–31.

Svantesson M, Löfmark R, Thorsén H, Kallenberg K, Ahlström G. Learning a way through ethical problems: Swedish nurses' and doctors' experiences from one model of ethics rounds. J Med Ethics. 2008;34:399–406.

Sulmasy LS, Bledsoe TA, ACP ethics, Professionalism and Human Rights Committee. American College of Physicians Ethics Manual: Seventh Edition. Ann Intern Med. 2019;170:S1–32.

Yaylaci S, Kitapcioglu D. Five-day simulated boot camp helps prepare medical students for transition to internship emergency medicine rotation. Eurasian J Med. 2015;14:49.

Ong YT, Kow CS, Teo YH, et al. Nurturing professionalism in medical schools. A systematic scoping review of training curricula between 1990-2019. Med Teach. 2020;42:636–49.

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank Fatih Artvinli, PhD, for his comments on the manuscript and the implementation. We are also grateful for Kamil Kayayurt MD, Guven Kirimli MD, and Esra Sezer, RN, MSc for their helpful contributions. We would also like to thank the staff of the Acibadem Mehmet Ali Aydinlar University Simulation Center (CASE) for their support, as well as our colleagues who put so much painstaking work into curricular development at the Acibadem Mehmet Ali Aydinlar University School of Medicine. Lastly, we would like to thank Erol Barbur, MD for his helpful assistance with language editing.

The authors have not received any kind of funding for the study.

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Department of Emergency Medicine, Acibadem Mehmet Ali Aydinlar University, School of Medicine, Istanbul, Turkey

Serpil Yaylaci, Suha Turkmen, Hasan Aldinc & Cem Gun

Department of History of Medicine and Ethics, Acibadem Mehmet Ali Aydinlar University, School of Medicine, Istanbul, Turkey

Yesim Isil Ulman

Department of Medical Education, Ege University, School of Medicine, İzmir, Turkey

Kevser Vatansever

Acibadem Mehmet Ali Aydinlar University, Graduate School of Health Sciences, Bioethics Master Program, Istanbul, Turkey

Gamze Senyurek

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Contributions

SY developed the main conception and the design of the study. She contributed to the data collection process, the data analyses, and discussing the results. She took part in the writing of the manuscript. YIU made significant contributions to the conception and design of the study. She led the ethical committee application process and the ethical conduct of the implementation. She contributed to the data collection process, the data analyses, and discussing the results. She elaborated on the manuscript and revised it critically. KV contributed to developing the methodology of the study, the data collection tool, and the design of the study. She conducted the statistical analyses and took part in interpreting the results. She took part in the writing of the manuscript and revised it critically. GS took part in the implementation of the study, contributed to the data collection tool and data analyses. She was also involved in drafting and revising the manuscript. ST took part in the implementation of the study, collecting the data, and contributed to organizing the drill, and debriefing process. HA took part in the implementation of the study, collecting the data, and contributed to organizing the drill, and debriefing process. CG took part in the implementation of the study, collecting the data, and contributed to organizing the drill, and debriefing process. All authors read and approved the final manuscript.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Serpil Yaylaci .

Ethics declarations

Ethics approval and consent to participate.

This study was approved by the Acibadem Mehmet Ali Aydinlar University Research Ethics Committee (ATADEK) with the decision number: 2018–2/68. The written informed consent was obtained from the participants before the practice.

Consent for publication

Not applicable.

Competing interests

The authors declare that they have no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher’s note.

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Supplementary Information

Additional file 1..

Drill scenarios, multiple-choice questions, and patient management problems.

Additional file 2.

 Research data.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article's Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article's Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ . The Creative Commons Public Domain Dedication waiver ( http://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/ ) applies to the data made available in this article, unless otherwise stated in a credit line to the data.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article.

Yaylaci, S., Ulman, Y.I., Vatansever, K. et al. Integrating patient management, reflective practice, and ethical decision-making in an emergency medicine intern boot camp. BMC Med Educ 21 , 536 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1186/s12909-021-02970-8

Download citation

Received : 28 January 2021

Accepted : 06 October 2021

Published : 22 October 2021

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1186/s12909-021-02970-8

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Clinical decision-making
  • Emergency medicine
  • Ethical reasoning
  • Reflective practice

BMC Medical Education

ISSN: 1472-6920

reflective essay on clinical decision making

  • Cancer Nursing Practice
  • Emergency Nurse
  • Evidence-Based Nursing
  • Learning Disability Practice
  • Mental Health Practice
  • Nurse Researcher
  • Nursing Children and Young People
  • Nursing Management
  • Nursing Older People
  • Nursing Standard
  • Primary Health Care
  • RCN Nursing Awards
  • Nursing Live
  • Nursing Careers and Job Fairs
  • CPD webinars on-demand
  • --> Advanced -->

reflective essay on clinical decision making

  • Clinical articles
  • CPD articles
  • CPD Quizzes
  • Practice question
  • Research in practice
  • A-Z of syndromes
  • Biological basis of child health
  • Expert advice
  • Career advice
  • Revalidation

Evidence and practice    

A nursing student’s reflective account of decision-making in a school nursing setting, bethaney squirrell children’s and young people’s nursing student, faculty of health and social sciences, bournemouth university, england, jane hunt senior lecturer, children’s and young people’s nursing, faculty of health and social sciences, bournemouth university, england.

Reflection is integral to professional revalidation and enhancing nursing practice; it is an art and a science to be learned. Learning the art of reflection begins as a student in clinical placement settings. Drawing on a reflective model, this article presents an account of one second-year children’s nursing student’s experiences in a community-based placement with a school nursing team. A school nurse appointment was reflected on where advice was offered to a 13-year-old student with sleep difficulties, low affect and lethargy, which included avoiding caffeinated drinks, reducing use of a laptop and mobile phone before going to sleep, and establishing a regular bedtime routine. Providing nursing care to this young person enabled the nursing student to improve their decision-making skills, become more self-aware, increase their confidence when communicating with a patient and reinforce the importance of applying theory to practice.

Nursing Children and Young People . doi: 10.7748/ncyp.2018.e1012

Squirrell B, Hunt J (2018) A nursing student’s reflective account of decision-making in a school nursing setting. Nursing Children and Young People. doi: 10.7748/ncyp.2018.e1012

This article has been subject to open peer review and has been checked for plagiarism using automated software

[email protected]

None declared

Published online: 03 May 2018

child health - education - reflection - revalidation - school nursing

User not found

Want to read more?

Already have access log in, 3-month trial offer for £5.25/month.

  • Unlimited access to all 10 RCNi Journals
  • RCNi Learning featuring over 175 modules to easily earn CPD time
  • NMC-compliant RCNi Revalidation Portfolio to stay on track with your progress
  • Personalised newsletters tailored to your interests
  • A customisable dashboard with over 200 topics

Alternatively, you can purchase access to this article for the next seven days. Buy now

Are you a student? Our student subscription has content especially for you. Find out more

reflective essay on clinical decision making

02 May 2024 / Vol 36 issue 3

TABLE OF CONTENTS

DIGITAL EDITION

  • LATEST ISSUE
  • SIGN UP FOR E-ALERT
  • WRITE FOR US
  • PERMISSIONS

Share article: A nursing student’s reflective account of decision-making in a school nursing setting

We use cookies on this site to enhance your user experience.

By clicking any link on this page you are giving your consent for us to set cookies.

Cognitive bias during clinical decision-making and its influence on patient outcomes in the emergency department: A scoping review

Affiliations.

  • 1 Faculty of Health, School of Nursing and Midwifery, University of Technology Sydney, Sydney, New South Wales, Australia.
  • 2 Neurology Department, Royal North Shore Hospital, St Leonards, New South Wales, Australia.
  • 3 Nursing and Midwifery Research Centre, Nursing and Midwifery Directorate, Northern Sydney Local Health District, Royal North Shore Hospital, St Leonards, New South Wales, Australia.
  • 4 Department of Intensive Care Medicine, Royal North Shore Hospital, St Leonards, New South Wales, Australia.
  • PMID: 37605250
  • DOI: 10.1111/jocn.16845

Background: An integral part of clinical practice is decision-making. Yet there is widespread acceptance that there is evidence of cognitive bias within clinical practice among nurses and physicians. However, how cognitive bias among emergency nurses and physicians' decision-making influences patient outcomes remains unclear.

Aim: The aim of this review was to systematically synthesise research exploring the emergency nurses' and physicians' cognitive bias in decision-making and its influence on patient outcomes.

Methods: This scoping review was guided by the PRISMA Extension for Scoping Reviews. The databases searched included CINAHL, MEDLINE, Web of Science and PubMed. No date limits were applied. The Patterns, Advances, Gaps, Evidence for practice and Research recommendation (PAGER) framework was used to guide the discussion.

Results: The review included 18 articles, consisting of 10 primary studies (nine quantitative and one qualitative) and eight literature reviews. Of the 18 articles, nine investigated physicians, five articles examined nurses, and four both physicians and nurses with sample sizes ranging from 13 to 3547. Six primary studies were cross-sectional and five used hypothetical scenarios, and one real-world assessment. Three were experimental studies. Twenty-nine cognitive biases were identified with Implicit bias (n = 12) most frequently explored, followed by outcome bias (n = 4). Results were inconclusive regarding the influence of biases on treatment decisions and patient outcomes. Four key themes were identified; (i) cognitive biases among emergency clinicians; (ii) measurement of cognitive bias; (iii) influence of cognitive bias on clinical decision-making; and (iv) association between emergency clinicians' cognitive bias and patient outcomes.

Conclusions: This review identified that cognitive biases were present among emergency nurses and physicians during clinical decision-making, but it remains unclear how cognitive bias influences patient outcomes. Further research examining emergency clinicians' cognitive bias is required.

Relevance to clinical practice: Awareness of emergency clinicians' own cognitive biases may result to the provision of equity in care.

No patient or public contribution in this review: We intend to disseminate the results through publication in a peer-reviewed journals and conference presentations.

Keywords: clinical decision-making; cognitive bias; emergency nurses; emergency physicians; implicit bias; patient outcomes.

© 2023 John Wiley & Sons Ltd.

Publication types

  • Clinical Decision-Making*
  • Databases, Factual
  • Emergency Service, Hospital*

U.S. flag

An official website of the United States government

The .gov means it’s official. Federal government websites often end in .gov or .mil. Before sharing sensitive information, make sure you’re on a federal government site.

The site is secure. The https:// ensures that you are connecting to the official website and that any information you provide is encrypted and transmitted securely.

  • Publications
  • Account settings

Preview improvements coming to the PMC website in October 2024. Learn More or Try it out now .

  • Advanced Search
  • Journal List

Logo of springeropen

Patient autonomy, clinical decision making, and the Phenomenological reduction

Jonathan lewis.

1 The Centre for Social Ethics and Policy, Department of Law, School of Social Sciences, The University of Manchester, Oxford Road, M13 9PL Manchester, UK

Søren Holm

2 Centre for Medical Ethics, Faculty of Medicine, University of Oslo, Oslo, Norway

Phenomenology gives rise to certain ontological considerations that have far-reaching implications for standard conceptions of patient autonomy in medical ethics, and, as a result, the obligations of and to patients in clinical decision-making contexts. One such consideration is the phenomenological reduction in classical phenomenology, a core feature of which is the characterisation of our primary experiences as immediately and inherently meaningful. This paper builds on and extends the analyses of the phenomenological reduction in the works of Husserl, Heidegger, and Merleau-Ponty in order to identify and explain its implications for our current understanding of the principle of respect for patient autonomy and the norms of clinical decision making.

For patients, being recognised as autonomous in the context of clinical decision making has normative significance for two reasons. Firstly, it sets the parameters within which they should be immune from paternalistic clinical interventions. In both medical law and biomedical ethics, informed consent is the standard mechanism through which a patient establishes the boundaries of her sovereignty (Archard 2008 ; Walker 2013 ; Lewis 2020 ). However, the right to partake in practices of informed consent (without third party involvement) is only extended to adult patients who are presumed to fulfil the demands of mental capacity. As Wayne Martin and Ryan Hickerson (2013) observe, capacity assessments in recent years have affirmed a particular approach to autonomy based on the satisfaction of conditions of competency linked to individual cognitive performance. For example, the test for incapacity in Sect. 3(1) of the Mental Capacity Act 2005 in England and Wales raises a strong, albeit negative, affirmation of the capacity for autonomy, whereby an individual is unable to make a decision if they are unable to understand, retain, use, or weigh information relevant to a decision or communicate that decision. The implication is that when a patient lacks deliberative competence capacities and thereby is taken to lack the capacity for autonomy, outside interference in the decision-making process is more likely to be justified.

“Competency,” “mental capacity,” and the “capacity for autonomy” are often treated as having the same meanings such that, on the basis of a certain amount of consensus amongst medical ethicists, a competent or capacitous individual is considered to have the “capacity for reason,” that is, “the capacities to comprehend information, critically reflect on and revise beliefs, and make a decision in the light of information” (Lewis 2021a , p. 16). Ultimately, the competency approach to autonomy in both medical law and ethics operates on the basis that individual cognitive capacities for reason are necessary constituents of a patient’s capacity for autonomous decision making in clinically related contexts (Foddy and Savulescu 2006 ; Holroyd 2009 ; Schaefer et al. 2014 ; Lewis 2021a ). When combined with liberal principles, the concept of the competent agent has been the backbone of regulatory and statutory approaches to medical decision making (Lewis 2021a , p. 16). However, the fact that an individual has been accorded the liberty to consent on the basis of her (presumed) competency/mental capacity does not guarantee that the consent she provides will be autonomous because there are no assurances that she has, as a matter of fact, understood or rationally deliberated on the information with which she has been informed or the knowledge she possesses. Thus, although satisfactory fulfilment of the conditions for competency (i.e., the capacity for reason) accounts for an individual’s autonomous agency (i.e., their capacity for autonomy ), it does not ensure that an individual makes an autonomous choice .

There is, therefore, a principled distinction between a patient’s capacity for autonomy and their exercise of autonomy (Lewis 2021a , b ), and this distinction will prove to be vital for understanding the implications of our approach to the phenomenological reduction for clinical decision making as well as the relationships between a more phenomenologically oriented approach to patient autonomy and traditional theories of autonomy, both of which are the focus of this paper. But before we broach this topic, it is important to acknowledge that this distinction points to a second reason why recognition of patient autonomy is normatively significant. Specifically, where the notion of autonomous choice or the exercise of autonomy is concerned, respect for autonomy allows competent patients to effect changes in their lives in a manner that is consistent with their values, desires, and motivations. As Coggon and Miola observe, when we are discussing whether an agent is exercising their autonomy, “there is a concern not just for the capacity for reason, but also for the effective use of it” (Coggon and Miola 2011 , p. 528). 1 In short, whether a patient’s exercise of their autonomy qualifies as “effective” will depend on “the soundness of her reasoning, given her own values” (ibid., p. 531) or, more broadly construed, the extent that she is the “power” behind whatever reasoning directly gives rise to her decisions, choices or actions (Buss and Westlund 2018 ). Although there are philosophical disagreements about what exactly constitutes “sound reasoning” and the nature of the “power” over such reasoning, the point is that an agent’s values, desires, and reasons “can be more or less autonomous depending on whether the processes or volitional structures by which they come to be developed are truly her own” (Lewis 2021a , p. 18). In terms of theories of autonomy, these processes and structures have traditionally been framed in purely cognitive terms, that is, as processes of introspective, critical reflection or as endorsements, identifications with, or rational responses to one’s values, desires, and motives by way of an appropriate cognitive mechanism (Christman 2004 ).

Conceptions of the autonomous patient as a cognitively capacitous, self-sufficient, and introspective individual, and associated theories of autonomy that appeal to rational reflection as the preeminent arbiter of autonomy, have been perceived as problematic, both conceptually and when applied in practice. Commentators have demonstrated that, when it comes to medical decisions, theories of autonomy that focus solely on the cognitive capacities for reason and conditions of rational reflection fail, in practice, to adequately capture the autonomy of certain individuals and groups despite individuals within those groups fulfilling the standards for mental capacity (Clough 2014 , 2017 ; Herring and Wall 2015 ; Lewis 2021b ). In addition, by discounting the impact of social and interpersonal relations on one’s exercises of autonomy (e.g., see Meyers 1989 ; Benson 1991 ; Mackenzie and Stoljar 2000 ; Meyers 2000 ; Friedman 2003 ; Christman 2004 ; 2009 ), appeals to traditional theories of autonomy preclude the possibility that other persons and social institutions may be obligated to help restore, support, or promote an individual’s autonomy (Mackenzie 2008 ; Dodds 2014 ; Mackenzie et al. 2014 ). As a result, theorists have argued for more relational accounts of autonomy (e.g., Meyers 2005 ; Mackenzie 2008 ; Westlund 2009 ; Anderson 2014 ; Mackenzie 2014 ; 2015 ; Westlund 2018 ), which are premised on an understanding of interpersonal and social relationships as—depending on the type of approach to relational autonomy—constitutive of autonomous agency or the background conditions that causally affect the exercise and achievement of autonomy (Mackenzie 2021 ). However, even though relational theorists are concerned with the ways in which interpersonal and social relations can support or undermine the conditions for autonomy, many of the most established accounts are still committed to a notion of autonomy understood purely as the exercise of certain cognitive capacities for reason (Meyers 2000 , 2005 ). It follows that while relational theorists reject the valorisation of the integrated, self-sufficient, and introspective individual, they – to varying degrees – share the non-relationalist’s commitment to the autonomous agent who turns her own attitudes into objects of reflection to determine how she will exercise her autonomy. 2

On the surface, phenomenology might be perceived to offer support for the sort of introspective reflection that constitutes an individual’s exercise of her capacity for autonomy. After all, as Gallagher ( 2012 , p. 58) notes, a standard objection to phenomenology is that it is a form of introspection and thereby a subjective exercise. However, this objection misses the point of classical phenomenology, as espoused by Husserl, Heidegger, and Merleau-Ponty (among others).

In this paper, we begin by demonstrating that this “introspective” interpretation of the nature of phenomenology is challenged by the notion of the “phenomenological reduction,” according to which, by suspending the natural way we tend to judge and look at reality, we acknowledge that our pre-reflective experiences of and in the world are inherently meaningful. Furthermore, the upshot of the phenomenological reduction is that such meaningfulness is encountered initially through first-person embodied and affective intentional experiences rather than through cognitive acts. As we will demonstrate, this calls into question the ability of non-relational and relational theories of autonomy, and their application in medical ethics and medical law, to fully capture patient autonomy, focused as they are on the satisfaction of cognitive conditions for mental capacity and the exercise of those capacities in acts of introspective, rational reflection, identification, or endorsement.

In section two, we argue that the phenomenological reduction, and a phenomenologically oriented approach to autonomy that it entails, cannot be entirely squared with traditional theories of autonomy. Moreover, and as we discuss in greater detail in section three, we also demonstrate that an approach to patient autonomy based on the phenomenological reduction is not compatible with exclusively relational accounts of autonomy. Therefore, one of novelties of this paper lies in the fact that it not only calls into question the practical adequacy of traditional theories of autonomy, and their application in medical ethics and medical law, but also that it does so without necessarily relying on a relational conception of autonomy. In addition, the analysis in section two challenges standard approaches to patient autonomy in clinical decision-making contexts. Our contribution to the literature on patient autonomy is based on an understanding of the ways in which the phenomenological reduction discloses how one makes sense of one’s autonomy-determining values, desires, and motivations at a pre-reflective level, particularly through moods, emotions, feelings, and active bodily engagements within our environments. We argue that not only are one’s capacities for affective and bodily intentional experience necessary components of one’s capacity for autonomy, but also one’s exercises of autonomy when making treatment decisions and choices are necessarily dependent upon, and can be constituted by, manifestations of one’s capacities for bodily and affective intentionality in certain affective states and skilful practices. Thus, we argue that not only is the phenomenological reduction a condition for the experience of autonomy and experience in general, but also the affective and embodied dimensions of experience can be integral parts of a patient’s exercise of their autonomy. Throughout sections two and three, we explain the key practical implications of the phenomenological reduction and affective and bodily intentional experience for clinical approaches to patient autonomy in medical decision making.

Phenomenological Reduction: Towards a Functional Definition

Before we explore the implications of the phenomenological reduction for clinical decision making and the relationships between a more phenomenologically oriented conception of autonomy and traditional theories of autonomy, we need to understand what the phenomenological reduction is and how it intervenes on questions of intentionality, experience, and, relatedly, the distinctions between rationality and irrationality, reason and emotion, and mind and body. This task is complicated by the fact that, when it comes to individual classical phenomenologists, not only are there conflicting interpretations of the phenomenological reduction, but also the respective approaches to the phenomenological reduction in, on the one hand, the works of Husserl and, on the other, those of Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty have traditionally been viewed as incompatible (Smith 2005 ). Since accounting for the nuances of and between these accounts and interpretations is beyond the scope of this paper, we attempt, in this section, to identify some common characteristics of the phenomenological reduction supported by exegetical work in the secondary literature. 3

As we shall explain in the next section, theories of autonomy that appeal solely to individual cognitive capacities, and the exercise of these capacities in rational reflection, are problematic not least because they preclude consideration of the affective and embodied dimensions of experience. The primary aim of this paper is to explain the ways in which non-cognitive capacities for experience, and the exercise of these capacities when they manifest as moods, feelings, emotions, and active bodily engagements, can be integral to a patient’s autonomy. On that basis, our characterisation of the phenomenological reduction relies more on the approaches adopted by Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty, for whom affectivity and embodied practical engagements are, in varying degrees, constitutive of phenomenologically reductive acts of sense-making, rather than those of Husserl or other classical phenomenologists.

It wouldn’t be appropriate to explicate this approach without briefly considering a core component of Husserl’s phenomenological reduction, to which both Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty responded. For Husserl, the phenomenological reduction is a technique, constituted by two devices, that provides us with access to the world of phenomena , as well as specific phenomena , in contrast to objective, mind-independent reality, which has been assumed to be the focus of scientific enquiry and epistemic claims made in the natural sciences. Broadly, there is a distinction to be made between the phenomenological way of looking at the world and the “natural” way (Husserl, 1982 § 32). Achievement of the former requires, firstly, a device by which we suspend or bracket the natural way in which we judge and look at reality ( epoché ), and, secondly, the reduction proper by which we (phenomenologically) inquire into an aspect of suspended reality (Smith 2005 , p. 555). According to Husserl, once we have bracketed the intentional content that comes with our “natural” way of judging and looking at reality, what is left is the “phenomenological residuum” of “absolute consciousness” (i.e., those aspects of our intentional acts and their contents that do not depend on the existence of a represented object “out there” in mind-independent reality) (Husserl, 1982 § 50).

Although it is common to claim that both Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty reject the phenomenological reduction, 4 more recently others have argued that they maintain the two devices employed by Husserl, namely, the epoché and the reduction proper (Smith 2005 ; Sheehan 2014 ). However, whereas Husserl’s conception of the phenomenological reduction entails phenomenological inquiries into intentional contents at the level of “absolute consciousness” (a matter that we do not need to take up here), Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty’s respective conceptions involve an understanding of intentionality, that is, the directedness or aboutness of our corporeal movements, perceptions, judgments, feelings, and thoughts, at the level of “being-in-the-world”. 5 Broadly speaking, we are meaningfully in the world and the world is meaningfully in us even before we turn it into an object of reflection.

According to Thomas Sheehan, based on Heidegger’s interpretation of intentionality in terms of “being,” “things out there in the universe come to be seen as meaningfully present phenomena: the perceived of a perception, the loved of an act of love, the judged of an act of judgment—that is, always in correlation with a human concern or practice” (Sheehan 2014 , p. 128). A phenomenon, according to Heidegger, is “that which shows itself as something showing itself” [emphasis added] (Heidegger, GA 63, p. 67). 6 In other words, and from an autonomy point of the view, even before one begins the process of reflecting on one’s values, desires, and motivations as part of one’s exercises of one’s autonomy, the phenomenological reduction implies that one has already recognised one’s values as values, as specific values, as one’s values, and as values that make sense in terms of the other attitudes and commitments that one holds as well as in terms of one’s lived experience. The point is that those aspects of oneself on which one draws to exercise one’s autonomy “are already operative in our everyday understanding” (Sheehan 2014 , p. 128). Thus, if, as we shall argue in section two, those dimensions of the self that allow one to meaningfully access one’s characteristics and dispositions on the basis of which one can lead a self-determining and self-governing life are factors on which one’s capacity for, and exercise of, autonomy are dependent, then the phenomenological reduction requires us, as bioethicists, medical ethicists, health practitioners, and patients, to pay attention to, and account for, the conditions and structures of the self that allow one to encounter “being” in general, and the “being” of phenomena in particular, in terms of their meaningfulness in our everyday lives. This leads us to the point that, for the early Heidegger, meaningfulness is encountered through practical action, specifically, contextualized, first-person, embodied and affective experience (Sheehan 2014 , pp. 128 − 30).

Like Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty rejected the idea of the phenomenological reduction as a reduction to “absolute consciousness” (Smith 2005 ). Indeed, many aspects of his approach to the phenomenological reduction echoed those of Heidegger: as he claimed, “Heidegger’s ‘ In‐der‐Welt‐Sein ’ [being-in-the-world] appears only against the background of the phenomenological reduction” (Merleau-Ponty 2002 , pp. xiii–xiv). Firstly, our most immediate and fundamental mode of access to the world is not a cognitive act (ibid., p. x). Secondly, there is no sharp distinction between the inner and the outer, between self and world (ibid., p. 407). Thirdly, when it comes to the meaningfulness of our engagements in the world, intentionality initially manifests in active bodily engagement (ibid., pp. 138-9).

In terms of attempting to standardise an approach to the phenomenological reduction that considers one’s affective and embodied (i.e., lived) experiences, the approach taken here, which characterises our primary experiences as inherently and immediately meaningful, calls into question the traditional philosophical distinctions between rational and irrational, reason and emotion, and mind and body, which also have tended to characterise accounts of autonomy in medical decision making. By encountering meaningfulness, we do not impose a subjective interpretation on empirical data, nor do we passively sense or represent some sort of independent and isolable entity that determines meaning (see, for example, Heidegger, GA 2, pp. 190-1; GA 63, p. 3; GA 45, p. 85). Detached reflection of phenomena, including reflections on those aspects of the self that traditionally have been deemed to constitute the standards for autonomous decision making, presuppose inherently meaningful encounters with those same phenomena. Indeed, according to Heidegger, that meaningfulness can become “distorted” through rational reflection (Heidegger GA 17, p. 288). To even turn our own autonomy-constituting values, desires and motivations into objects of reflection is to already acknowledge the inherent meaningfulness of those attitudes and, consequently, the dependence of such reflective inquiry on our meaningful access to objects, which can be constituted as much by “irrational” feelings, emotions, moods, and bodily movements as by “rational” understanding (Heidegger, GA 2, p. 210). Central to phenomenological conceptions of autonomy, on which we are attempting to shed light, is the idea that, prior to taking up a detached reflective stance towards our own selves and each other, we are always already corporeally and affectively engaged in the world. Perception, bodily comportment, and reflection are (in varying degrees) embodied and skilful activities that allow us to cope with the world. 7

Pre-reflective Awareness and Bodily and Affective Intentionality

The conviction that is at work in our functional characterisation of the phenomenological reduction – one that is, in varying degrees, shared by classical phenomenologists – is that detached reflective self-awareness is only possible because there is a prior pre-reflective self-awareness built into experience. In autonomy terms, one’s motivating attitudes are always already meaningful even before one comes to reflect on or rationally respond to them. Furthermore, at least from Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty’s respective points of view, the upshot of the phenomenological reduction is that such meaningfulness is not immediately or fundamentally the result of a cognitive act, but, as intentional content (in the sense that it is “perpetually directed” at some “goal” or “project of the world” (Merleau-Ponty 2002 , p. xx)), primarily manifests in bodily engagement and practical action. 8 Indeed, for Heidegger, it also manifests through our affective experiences in the world. In this section, we extend the analyses of the phenomenological reduction in the works of Merleau-Ponty and Heidegger in order to explain the relationships between the capacities for bodily and affective intentional experience and the capacity for autonomy. In addition, we illustrate the ways in which manifestations of bodily and affective intentionality in terms of skilful, practical coping and moods, emotions, and feelings relate to exercises of autonomy. Finally, for both bodily intentionality and affective intentionality, we highlight some of the key implications for clinical decision making when it is recognised that autonomy is, in part, necessarily dependent upon the capacities for bodily and affective intentional experience and the exercise of those capacities.

Bodily Intentionality and Autonomy

Pre-reflective self-awareness and the unity with the world that it encompasses is often to be understood in terms of one’s practical coping with the world (Crowell 2013 , p. 174; Gallagher 2012 , p. 78). An individual is intentionally involved with and in the world through active bodily engagements that cannot be equated with the deliberative outcome of her desires and beliefs. This approach to bodily intentionality, which Hubert Dreyfus finds in Merleau-Ponty and the early Heidegger, has been labelled as “absorbed coping,” that is, “the experience of a steady flow of skilful activity in response to one’s sense of the environment” whereby “one’s body is solicited by the situation to get into the right relation to it,” “something like what athletes call flow, or playing out of their heads” (Dreyfus 2014 , p, 81; also see, Dreyfus 2000 ). As Wrathall ( 2015 , p. 195) observes, “highly skilled, fluid actions are experienced…as being drawn out of me directly and spontaneously by the particular features of the situation, without the mediation of occurrent mental or psychological states or acts.” Challenging overly cognitive conceptions of autonomy, Meyers ( 2005 , p. 40) makes a similar point; embodied engagement is a form of “practical intelligence,” yet one that “people seldom exercise self-consciously.” The point is that when we are “in the flow,” there is no cognitive disengagement between one’s behaviour and one’s surroundings; an individual is one with their setting and thereby aware of the skilfulness and unity of their body. In one sense, then, bodily intentionality can be taken to be the condition of “unity,” “equilibrium,” or “poise” in one’s environment (Kong 2017 , pp. 78–81).

Kong ( 2017 , pp. 51–99) has demonstrated the importance of the phenomenology of absorbed skilful coping for autonomy considerations in mental capacity assessments, particularly when such considerations involve cognitively-impaired patients who may be unable to satisfy the standard cognitive demands of capacity law. She argues that absorbed coping, like autonomy, is normatively significant in that “there is a sense of satisfaction when we manage to achieve it” (ibid., p. 80). Relatedly, in seeking to develop a phenomenology of illness, Fredrik Svenaeus argues that, on the basis of their illness, a patient’s body is experienced simultaneously as their own yet alien – obtrusively presenting itself to the patient as “broken” and “no longer under control” (2000b, p. 131). For Svenaeus, and based, in part, on what he considers to be an unorthodox interpretation of Heidegger’s concept of “ Unheimlichkeit ” as “unhomelikeness,” not only is illness an “uncanny” or “unhomelike” way of being-in-the-world (Svenaeus 2000a , b ), but also the idea of “fixing” a patient means supporting her “back to a homelike being-in-her-own-body” (Svenaeus 2000b , p. 134). Echoing these points, Meyers ( 2005 , p. 39) observes that “alienation from the body brought on by physical pain, illness, or injury” can be “profoundly disorienting.” Viewed in this light, not only do “ingrained bodily configurations and habitual bodily practices help to preserve one’s sense of self” (ibid.), but also, Meyers argues, authentic traits, affects, values, and desires (i.e., those attitudes that underlie one’s exercises of autonomy) can be “enacted” through absorbed coping in a way that “gives people the sense of wholeness that is characteristic of autonomy” (ibid., pp. 45 − 6). These comments raise the question of the nature of the relationship between, on the one hand, bodily intentionality, which is non-cognitive to the extent that it does not involve rational reflection on one’s values, desires, and motivations, and, on the other, those cognitive capacities and acts that have traditionally been the focus of philosophers and medical ethicists in accounts of autonomy. It is to this question that we now turn.

In light of a case study involving a severely autistic adolescent, not only does Kong observe how detached reflection can disrupt the flow of absorbed coping and the experienced equilibrium with the world, she illustrates how stereotyped or repetitive motor movements – acknowledged as “stimming” by autistic adults – serve as a crucial coping strategy for affective distress and the experience of bodily disunity (Kong 2017 , pp. 51–99). Theoretical perspectives have suggested that individuals with autism find it difficult to govern their thoughts and actions because of excessive, insufficient, and inefficient sensory processing and perceptual inconstancy (Kapp, Steward, Crane et al., 2019 , pp. 1782-3). Autistic adults have reported exhibiting repetitive, usually rhythmic bodily movements and vocalisations in response to distorted or overstimulating perceptions and dysregulated, excessive, or distracting thoughts, all of which are very often triggered by confusing, unpredictable, and overwhelming environments (ibid., p. 1786). They claim that stimming not only allows them to cope with their environments , but also affords them a level of control over their body, their affective states, and their thoughts (ibid., pp. 1788-9).

Psychological and theoretical perspectives on autism seem to validate the phenomenological principle that active bodily engagement, characterised above in terms of absorbed coping, is a necessary condition for meaningful pre-reflective experience. The point is that certain unpredictable or overstimulating environments disrupt the “equilibrium” or “poise” that individuals with autism would otherwise have in their environments, leading to experiences of bodily, affective, and reflective disunity (Kong 2017 ; Kapp, Steward, Crane et al., 2019 ). Viewed accordingly, stimming functions as a compensatory means of (re)establishing the “flow-like” experience of skilfully engaging with, and responding to, the environment, and, on that basis, affords a level of control over cognitive acts that, from an autonomy perspective, govern actions and choices (Kapp, Steward, Crane et al., 2019 ).

Although these discussions concerning the bodily intentionality of individuals with autism have specific implications for how phenomenological concepts could be employed in clinical decision-making contexts involving cognitively-impaired or neurodiverse patients, these implications lie beyond the scope of the current paper. Nevertheless, the principle that certain bodily movements – in this case, stimming – can re-establish a sense of bodily unity also extends to general clinical situations in which an ill patient should be supported by healthcare practitioners to experience “homelike being-in-her-own-body” such that her body “once again attains a central place in the patterns that make out her being-in-the-world” (Svenaeus 2000b , p. 134). As Meyers observes, one way in which experiences of bodily alienation resulting from pain, illness, or injury can be overcome is by, if possible, re-establishing “ingrained bodily configurations and habitual bodily practices” (Meyers 2005 , p. 39), In terms of autonomy, then, a patient’s capacities for active bodily engagement or absorbed coping are not only, when interpreted in the context of the phenomenological reduction, necessary for pre-reflective self-awareness and inherently meaningful experience in general, but also necessary components of the capacity for autonomy (i.e., autonomous agency). In principle, individuals without those capacities would be unable to achieve the level of unity, equilibrium, or poise needed for reflective self-awareness.

As mentioned previously, there are principled reasons to distinguish between the capacity for autonomy and the exercise of autonomy. In terms of the latter, not only does the phenomenological reduction entail that bodily intentionality is necessary to meaningfully access the values, desires, and motivations to which one responds in exercising one’s autonomy, Meyers suggests that absorbed coping “enacts” these motivating attitudes in a way characteristic of the exercise of autonomy (Meyers 2005 , pp. 45 − 6). For both Kong ( 2017 , p. 80) and Meyers ( 2005 , p. 46), bodily intentionality is normatively significant to the extent that it provides the conditions by which one can skilfully and intelligently navigate and respond to one’s environment in a way that is self-satisfying, or, according to Svenaeus ( 2000b , p. 134), by which one can experience “homelike being-in-one’s-own-body”. The fact that one finds lived bodily unity to be satisfying or “homelike” implies that the attainment of the state of “being-in-one’s-own-body” is something that one values, a value on which one will act at the pre-reflective level. Not only does this mean that bodily intentionality as it manifests in active bodily engagement is a necessary component of autonomous agency, but also it entails that the skills expressed through absorbed coping are, in part, constitutive of exercises of autonomy. Furthermore, these skills, as practical intelligence, not only respond to the value of lived bodily unity, they, as Meyers ( 2005 , p. 48) argues, also can function to review, re-review, validate or disown other values, desires, and motivations. This non-cognitive dimension of the exercise of autonomy is often non-existent in abstract discussions regarding the conditions for autonomy typically found in traditional accounts. Nevertheless, in clinical reality, when practitioners are faced with patients who are experiencing a sense of bodily disunity as a result of pain, illness, or injury, the enactment of skills expressed through absorbed coping in a way that responds to a patient’s own values could be vital to the exercise of her autonomy. As Meyers claims, “we define ourselves as we act, and we cannot redefine ourselves without altering our patterns of action:” this “vocabulary is a trenchant vehicle for communicating avowal and disavowal and for advocating either persisting in or altering one’s course” (Meyers 2005 , p. 46).

In terms of the implications of accepting bodily intentionality as a necessary component of the capacity for autonomy, and as a component, and constitutive of exercises of autonomy, firstly, the previous analysis suggests that clinicians should be attentive to the features of a patient’s search for equilibrium at the level of active bodily engagements in her environment. On the one hand, as Svenaeus ( 2000b , p. 134) argues, this means that treatments and healthcare support should strive to ensure that a patient can once again feel at home in her own body such that it “once again attains a central place in the patterns that make out her being-in-the-world” (even if such ways of being-in-the-world end up being drastically altered as a result of long-term or permanent changes to the patient’s lived bodily experiences as a result of her illness). On the other hand, if a patient is displaying bodily movements or vocalisations that a clinician might initially perceive to be heteronomous or irrational, then this could indicate that the patient is experiencing bodily or affective distress. Such distress could, in part, come down to the patient’s response to her illness, to proposed medical interventions, or to clinical decision making in general. It could also be the result of interactions between a patient and their clinician. And this idea finds conceptual support in Merleau-Ponty’s notion of intercorporeity , according to which the intentional contents of one’s bodily engagement “are not just formed in one’s individual body as the result of an isolated subjective process but depend in a dynamic way on the other’s elicitations and responses” (Gallagher 2012 , pp. 199–200). Not only would it seem like good clinical practice for clinicians and healthcare staff to ensure that patients do not experience any undue stress caused by the clinical decision-making encounter, but also, on the basis that the model of Shared Decision Making (SDM) is now the de facto health policy standard for many national health providers (Lewis 2020 ), it is in the interests of both clinicians and their patients to ensure that the latter are supported by a decision-making environment that allows them to exert a level of control over their body and affective states in order to exercise their autonomy.

Secondly, if we accept Meyers’ argument that the skills displayed by individuals though absorbed coping can enact their values, desires, and motivations in a way characteristic of the exercise of autonomy (Meyers 2005 , pp. 45 − 6), then there is an autonomy-based reason for practitioners to facilitate decision-making encounters that allow patients to exercise those skills and that provide the former with the opportunity to understand those skills and their relations to underlying values. This would involve operationalising the concepts of bodily intentionality and the conditions of absorbed coping for application in SDM contexts (for an example of how such concepts could be operationalised in the context of mental capacity assessments, see Kong 2017 , pp. 51–99).

Thirdly, the phenomenology of absorbed coping provides a principled basis for calling into question attempts to eliminate motor stereotypies in both capacitous and incapacitated patients, attempts which remain popular both clinically and in research (Kapp, Steward, Crane et al., 2019 ). This coincides with the recent call for well-informed clinicians to pay greater attention to the “lived experiences” of patients living with long-term motor disabilities or somatic illnesses in order to facilitate interventions that allow them to lead fulfilling and autonomous lives with their symptoms (Humpston and Broome 2020 ) or that allow them to feel as “homelike” as possible in a new and different form of being-in-the-world than the one present before the onset of illness (Svenaeus 2000b , p. 135).

Affective Intentionality and Autonomy

Turning now to the affective dimension of intentional experience and its relationship to autonomy, the point we should recall from earlier is that, according to typical theories of autonomy, whether and to what extent an individual can be said to “authentically” exercise their autonomy when making decisions and choices depends on whether and to what extent the values, desires, and motivations on which she reflects are her own. Similarly, at least according to more phenomenological readings, 9 Heidegger, in working out his notion of authenticity, looks for those attitudes and experiences in which we discover ourselves to be an ineliminable ground of our decisions and actions. For Heidegger, the primary instances where we have the chance to see ourselves in this way are when we feel experience anxiety, when we are no longer gripped by social norms, and when we are conscious of our need to take responsibility (Braver 2014 , p. 89; Crowell 2013 , p. 204; Wrathall 2015 , p. 206). 10 From a phenomenological perspective, these experiences cognitively disengage us from our everyday fluid, skilful practices of absorbed coping, and entail that we must choose to make a choice and thereby take responsibility for our lives, which Heidegger calls “resoluteness” (Heidegger, GA 2, p. 297). Nevertheless, as we have already demonstrated, the reflective acts that these experiences entail still depend on bodily intentionality and the skills expressed through absorbed coping: “I articulate courses of action – weighing evidence and considering reasons for going on in one way or another” [emphasis added] (Crowell 2013 , p. 202).

Transposing this idea into clinical decision-making contexts, when a patient suffers from a chronic illness, she may be, for pathophysiological reasons, unable to fluidly respond to the demands and solicitations of her environment in ways typical of her usual being-in-the-world. Accordingly, a patient may decide to choose the intervention that best restores the meaningful way she engaged with and in the world prior to becoming ill thereby maintaining her practical identity. For instance, if the patient is suffering from early-stage amyotrophic lateral sclerosis (“ALS”), she might choose a direct cognitive intervention, such as a brain-computer interface, on the basis that it can purportedly re-establish her capacities for absorbed coping and thereby maintain those skills expressive of her practical identity. Alternatively, a patient may decide to commit to a different way of being in the world and thereby choose the intervention that would best establish a new practical identity. For example, a patient who develops schizophrenia might choose to avoid clinical interventions that focus solely on correcting thoughts and perceptions in order to explore therapies that allow him to lead a fulfilling life with, yet in better control of, his symptoms. 11 Whatever attitude the patient holds towards their practical identity, and, accordingly, whichever treatment option she chooses, the point is that when a patient meets with her physician in order to discuss treatment options, the cognitive disengagement from her active bodily engagements means that, at the cognitive level, she can choose to take those values that she initially disclosed at a pre-reflective level as “a reason for an action that necessarily figures in the explanation of that action as an action” (Wrathall 2015 , 206).

On the face of it, Heidegger’s phenomenological approach to authentic, reflective self-awareness may appear to affirm more traditional conceptions of autonomy: it acknowledges that the capacity for reason is a necessary condition for the exercise of an individual’s authority over her actions; it recognises that an agent with the capacity for reason is able to effect changes in her life in a manner that is consistent with the sort of practical identity she would want to adopt; and it acknowledges that authentic choices are intentional and free from the direct grip of external influences. However, Heidegger is sceptical of our ability to cognitively control how we exercise our capacity for reason. As Braver ( 2014 , p. 90) suggests, “even the limited form of autonomy that resoluteness can achieve is not something I can give myself.” For Heidegger, the point is that our power to exercise our autonomy is dependent on affective intentionality, that is, when it manifests in moods.

According to Heidegger, moods are “fleeting experiences that ‘colour’ one’s whole ‘psychical condition’” (Heidegger, GA 2, p. 450). Consequently, moods call into question the centrality of rational, introspective reflection in traditional approaches to autonomy. Rather than accept that reason belongs to thought alone, feelings and emotions are much more “rational” than we first thought (Heidegger, GA 5, pp. 5–10). This is because moods, emotions, and feelings, which Heidegger does not consistently distinguish between, not only determine how and in what way we react to the world and others, they are fundamentally entwined with the process by which we exercise our capacity for reason in authentic decision-making contexts. In short, moods are beyond the scope of rational reflection and self-governance because they are a condition of both. The upshot of Heidegger’s account of the conditions for authentic choice is that it reveals significant limits to our ability to cognitively determine how we exercise our autonomy. The phenomenological reduction and the phenomenological approach to moods “emphasises our passivity;” “we find ourselves in a mood not of our making or of our choice, and we can’t change our mood simply by deciding to do so” (Braver 2014 , p. 53).

In clinical situations, a patient will not usually find herself affectively inert when she comes to make decisions and treatment choices. Under the influence of pain or drugs, or in response to a specific health condition or proposed medical intervention, she may temporarily experience shock, fear, panic, or fatigue during the clinical encounter. 12 The point that we can take from Heidegger is that lived affective experience through moods, feelings, and emotions affect the way we make sense of our values, desires, and motivations when we reflect on or respond to them in exercises of our autonomy. “Good moods” may help us to perceive our attitudes as things that we really want to respond to and which we deem to be warranted and deserving of respect. Conversely, “bad moods” may lead us to feel alienated from our motivating attitudes or lead us to repudiate our values. As with bodily intentionality, not only does this mean that affective intentionality is a necessary component of the capacity for autonomy, but also it entails that moods, emotions, and feelings, which manifest affective intentionality, are, in part, constitutive of exercises of autonomy in the sense that they can function to approve or disown those motivating attitudes on which authentic choice is based.

Despite the fact our ability to control our moods and affective attitudes is limited, they can be affected indirectly by altering aspects of the meaningful contexts and relationships in which we find ourselves. This idea has received support in the relational autonomy literature.

Specifically, recognising the fact that malign interpersonal relationships can causally contribute to a patient’s inability to exhibit the necessary positive affective attitudes towards herself, Mackenzie ( 2008 ) argues that it is the physician’s obligation to empathise with the patient and support her to experience those affective attitudes that allow her to esteem, respect, or recognise her values as meaningful or valuable. The point that Svenaeus ( 2000b , p. 134) makes regarding health practitioners’ obligations to support the patient to return to a homelike being-in-the-world through the help of medicine also applies here. From a phenomenological perspective, achievement of the latter could be supported by facilitating a clinical decision-making environment that allows the patient to experience those moods and emotions through which she normally makes sense of the world in terms of her everyday lived experiences, and this may extend to affective attitudes of trust, esteem, and/or respect for herself, her motivating attitudes, and her decisions (Meynen 2011 ). In addition, if, as with bodily intentionality, a patient’s capacity for autonomy and the exercise of that autonomy are necessarily dependent on certain moods, emotions, and feelings, then it would seem like good clinical practice for clinicians and healthcare staff to ensure that patients do not experience any undue affective distress during the clinical decision-making encounter. Furthermore, given, as Svenaeus ( 2000b , pp. 134-5) suggests, that bringing a patient back to “homelikeness” such that she no longer experiences her own body in an obtrusively alien way may require her to adopt a new and different being-in-the-world and thereby a new and different practical identity, such an approach to clinical practice does not rule out the possibility of extending the decision-making process over several clinical encounters. As Martin and Hickerson ( 2013 , p. 212) observe, this would ensure that due regard is given to a patient’s “temporal capacities” to “knit together [her] past experiences in such a way as to project [herself] meaningfully into an uncertain and existentially open future.” Furthermore, and although an affectively- and bodily-oriented conception of autonomy would, in principle, allow for authentic patient decisions that, from the outside, may appear to be irrational, heteronomous, or anomalous, a temporal approach that extends the decision-making process over several clinical encounters may, for clinicians concerned about whether a patient is genuinely exercising their autonomy, serve to illustrate that a patient’s judgments regarding their values, desires, and motivation are rational and authentic, and not subject to external or internal autonomy-undermining influences.

Phenomenological Autonomy or Relational Autonomy?

It has been suggested that the phenomenological reduction validates the relational turn in the analysis of the concept of autonomy (Kong 2017 , p. 81). We should recall that relational accounts of autonomy are premised on an understanding of interpersonal and social relationships as either constitutive of autonomous agency or the background conditions that causally affect the exercise and achievement of autonomy (Mackenzie 2021 ). In this final section, we consider the question of whether and the phenomenologically oriented approach to autonomy, which the phenomenological reduction entails, demands a commitment to relational autonomy.

In the previous discussions concerning Heidegger’s notion of authenticity, which grounds one’s decisions and choices in one’s being-in-the-world, we observed that, when it comes to medical decisions, a patient might choose a treatment option that best maintains the practical identity she had before she became ill. Alternatively, she might choose to pursue a new practical identity. Both approaches are compatible with Heidegger’s notion of authenticity. However, even if a patient wishes to re-establish or maintain her practical identity through medical treatment, there may be certain instances where, in the eyes of clinicians, such a practical identity appears to be heteronomous or irrational when considered in the light of current Western clinical and socio-cultural norms. For instance, commentators have highlighted the conflicts between the typical standards of modern, Western clinical practice and medicine and the “way of life” that grounds the practical identities of Ultra-Orthodox Jewish patients (Glick et al. 2011 ; Gabbay et al. 2017 ). Patient practices and behaviours based on Orthodox observance of “Halacha,” a practical code derived from the Hebrew Bible and the canon of rabbinic literature, can extend to avoidance of medical treatment or refraining from asking for healthcare assistance on the Sabbath, deference to rabbinic authority on the choice of intervention, family consultation in clinical decision making, and declining treatment or referral in cases of psychiatric illness (Gabbay et al. 2017 ). In addition, certain medical interventions, such as withholding of life-sustaining treatments in clinically futile cases, fertility therapy, invasive and non-invasive prenatal testing, abortions for foetal anomalies or maternal conditions, contraception, and the use of nonkosher products in medical care, may be deemed to conflict, or require reconciliation with the Halachic code (Glick et al. 2011 ). Even then, the delineation between Halachic and medical opinion is considered to be a complex and controversial topic (ibid.). For healthcare practitioners lacking in specific cultural competence or who do not seek to inquire about the unique religious, spiritual, and cultural factors that contribute to an Ultra-Orthodox Jewish patient’s practical identity, such approaches to medical treatments and clinical decision making may be perceived as irrational or symptoms of the patient’s condition, confused with a mental condition, or indicative of an absence of patient autonomy (Gabbay et al. 2017 ).

Relatedly, a clinician’s questioning of the rationality and the authenticity of a patient’s choice of treatment may also arise when, regardless of her specific religious, cultural, or social characteristics, she chooses to pursue a new practical identity. As Meyers ( 2005 , p. 41) argues, a problem with applying principles of autonomy that appeal to rational reflection as its preeminent arbiter is that these principles provide scope to call into question the autonomy of “anomalous” decisions in the sense that they are perceived as departures from “certified patterns of behaviour:” “only after such anomalous behaviour had been scrutinized and judged to be expressive of authentic traits, affects, values, and desires could similar future behaviour count as autonomous.”

These issues emphasise the need for physicians and medical staff to be attentive to their patient’s search for equilibrium in her lived experiences, through which she displays skilful bodily engagements that constitute her practical identity, and which can enact those values, desires, and motivations that inform her choice of treatment. According to Kong ( 2017 , p. 184; pp. 194-5), a physician’s attentiveness to the ways in which a patient’s illness has affected her practical identity and thereby her ability to fluidly cope with the world in the way she would want will help to establish a “shared perceptual understanding” on the basis of which a patient’s choices and associated reasons can be identified. Without these bonds of commonality, there is no possibility for seemingly “discordant” behaviour or “anomalous” treatment choices to be recognised as anything other than irrational or heteronomous. This can be damaging, particularly for patients with motor disabilities or somatic illnesses, or for patients who adopt practical identities in accordance with their specific cultural or religious values that seem incompatible with the general norms governing modern clinical practice and medical treatment. It can not only lead to clinical encounters that generate conflict and undue bodily, affective or reflective distress and disunity (see, for example, Gabbay et al. 2017 ), and pave the way for therapeutic interventions that seek to correct seemingly irrational behaviour thereby “entrench[ing] oppressive, disabling practices” (Kong 2017 , p. 185), but also disregard, constrain, or manipulate a patient’s practical identity and thereby her ways of engaging and coping with the world (ibid., p. 197). In addition, it implies a failure on the part of the physician to recognise the patient as someone who has the status of autonomy. This can disable the patient’s ability to exercise her autonomy and, simultaneously, facilitates the conditions for unwarranted paternalistic intervention (Lewis 2021b ).

What these discussions demonstrate is that a phenomenological approach to the exercise of autonomy (i.e., one that takes into account the relationships between affective and bodily intentionality and authentic choice) is compatible with one particular approach to relational autonomy, that is, one that includes causal relational conditions for autonomy (Holroyd 2009 ). The point is that although one may fulfil the affective, bodily, and cognitive conditions for autonomous agency, how one exercises one’s autonomy when making choices and decisions will, in part, depend on interpersonal relationships, including whether a clinician takes into account a patient’s practical identity as it relates to her autonomy, whether a clinician respects the exercises of a patient’s autonomy, and whether a clinician recognises the patient as someone who has the status of being an autonomous agent. Furthermore, to the extent that a patient’s capacities for bodily and affective engagement are, when interpreted in the context of the phenomenological reduction, necessary for reflective engagement with one’s values and thereby necessary for the capacity for autonomy (i.e., autonomous agency), by facilitating clinical decision-making environments that generate undue bodily, affective, or cognitive distress, clinicians can contribute to a patient’s inability to fulfil the conditions for the capacity for autonomy. What makes such accounts of autonomy causally relational is that, as Christman ( 2004 ) demonstrates, interpersonal relationships contribute to an agent’s psychological states (and, as we have sought to demonstrate in this article, their affective states and embodied experience) and are thereby part of the “background requirements” for autonomy. In other words, certain interpersonal relations might cause an agent to fulfil or fail to meet the cognitive and non-cognitive conditions for autonomous agency or choice (Holroyd 2009 ).

Relational accounts of autonomy do not only consist of the causal variety (Mackenzie 2021 ). An account is considered to be “exclusively,” “uniquely,” or “thoroughly” relational if it posits particular normative social and interpersonal relationships as “conceptually necessary requirements of autonomy” (Christman 2004 , p. 147). A thoroughly relational view of autonomy presumes the metaphysical claim that autonomy is a property of the relations that comprise social conditions in which an agent is embedded (ibid., p, 159). If that is the case, then being autonomous means not only satisfying the first-person capacities for autonomy, but also being embedded in the right kinds of social conditions with the right kinds of interpersonal relationships. Rather than causally relational, such accounts are taken to be “constitutively” relational (Holroyd 2009 ).

There is nothing in or entailed by the phenomenological reduction to suggest that certain social and interpersonal conditions are necessary, as constitutive conditions, for a phenomenologically oriented conception of autonomous agency. As we have seen, the phenomenological reduction implies that one has, prior to reflective engagement, already pre-reflectively experienced one’s values as values, as specific values, and as one’s values through the manifestation of one’s bodily and affective intentionality. In other words, the phenomenological reduction is the basis of experience and, accordingly, the experience of autonomy. Neither making sense of one’s experience by employing the phenomenological reduction nor the exercises of those bodily and affective capacities that provide pre-reflective, meaningful access to aspects of oneself to which one responds when making decisions and choices require one to stand in any particular social or interpersonal relationship. Furthermore, it is implausible that the phenomenological reduction necessitates constitutive social conditions for one to either experience cognitive disengagement from one’s everyday absorbed coping through which one discovers oneself to be the ground of one’s decisions and actions, or to decide upon a treatment choice in response to those grounds disclosed at a pre-reflective level. As we have seen, a patient can be seen to make “anomalous” decisions and exhibit “discordant” or “inconsistent” behaviour, or pre-reflectively experience their values, desires, and motivations through embodied engagements and affective states that appear heteronomous or irrational. On the basis of the phenomenological reduction, these are all compatible with phenomenological conceptions of the conditions for autonomy and authentic choice.

The phenomenological reduction implies that moods and embodied practical coping are vital to the disclosure of the meanings of things, people, and events. In autonomy terms, this means that even before one begins the process of reflecting on one’s values, desires, and motivations as part of one’s exercises of one’s autonomy, one has pre-reflectively experienced one’s values as values, as specific values, as one’s values, and as values that make sense in terms of one’s practical identity. On that basis, and by extending the analyses of the phenomenological reduction in the works of Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty, this paper has argued that the affective and embodied dimensions of experience are, in principle, integral parts of a patient’s capacity for, and exercise of autonomy, and should, therefore, be accorded appropriate recognition by healthcare providers and practitioners in decision-making contexts. These arguments reveal that traditional individualistic theories of autonomy, relational theories, and standard accounts of autonomy in biomedical ethics and medical law, to the extent that they assume that autonomy is purely conditioned by cognitive capacities and processes of introspective self-reflection, are, in practice, ill-suited to fully capture patient autonomy, particularly when patients’ experiences of pain, illness, or injury result in experiences of bodily or affective distress or disunity. Finally, whereas some have suggested that the phenomenological reduction validates a relational conception of autonomy, we argued that a phenomenological approach to autonomy, grounded as it is by the phenomenological reduction, is not compatible with relational autonomy when the latter assumes that interpersonal and social relationships are constitutive conditions of autonomy.

Statements and Declarations

No ethical approval necessary.

Competing Interests

There are no conflicts of interest.

1 According to Tom Beauchamp and James Childress ( 2013 , pp. 104-5), a patient’s choices are rendered autonomous when they are made intentionally, free from controlling influences and with adequate understanding of medically-relevant information. Adequate understanding is also a core component of the General Medical Council’s ethical guidance.

2 There, are, of course, exceptions in the relational literature. According to “strong substantivists” (see, for example, Oshana 1998 ), an individual’s endorsement of, identification with, or rational response to attitudes, beliefs, and reasons is largely irrelevant if she does not commit to an externally defined, non-authoritarian value structure. However, the majority of relational theorists do not share the conviction that social conditions are constitutively necessary conditions of personal autonomy.

3 To this end, we rely on the approaches adopted in the Anglo-American tradition of phenomenological exegesis by Lee Braver, Steven Crowell, Thomas Sheehan and Mark Wrathall.

4 On the basis that Husserl’s notion of the phenomenological reduction seems to require a retraction from the world, it has often been held that Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty’s respective commitments to the notion of “being-in-the-world” are incompatible with the phenomenological reduction.

5 As Smith ( 2005 , n. 3) observes, although Merleau-Ponty’s conception of “ être au monde ” should not be conflated with Heidegger’s “ In‐der‐Welt‐Sein ”, there are obvious affinities between the two. Here, we employ a notion of “being-in-the-world” based on those affinities, rather than account for the specific interpretive nuances of and between the two.

6 This idea is also found in Husserl’s work, who claims that consciousness is consciousness of something as something in the sense that our engagements with phenomena deliver an “interpretive sense” (Husserl 2001 , 121).

7 This is in contrast with, for example, the interpretation of perception as an intermediary in a two-step, realist epistemological model, whereby passive receptions of something like sense data are synthesised as representations of external objects.

8 See, for example, Merleau-Ponty ( 2002 , p. 162): “Our bodily experience of movement is not a particular case of knowledge; it provides us with a way of access to the world and the object, with a ‘ praktognosia ’, which has to be recognised as original and perhaps as primary.”

9 Here, we draw attention to the distinction between more phenomenological readings of Heidegger, as provided by Lee Braver, Steven Crowell, Thomas Sheehan and Mark Wrathall, and “layer-cake” pragmatist readings adopted by, for example, Hubert Dreyfus, Mark Okrent, and John Haugeland. According to “layer-cake” interpretations, our meaningful, norm-governed, practical coping is both pre-predicative and nonconceptual and, therefore, distinct from assertoric and propositional intentionality.

10 For a discussion of how this sort of disengagement from one’s everyday being-in-the-world that is necessary for authentic understanding relates to the “uncanny” or “unhomelike” disengagement from one’s lived body, which one experiences through illness, see Svenaeus 2000b , pp. 127–131.

11 See, for example, Humpston and Broome 2020 .

12 At common law, it has been held that such “temporary factors” may lead to a temporary erosion of a patient’s capacity for autonomy (see, for example, Re MB (Medical Treatment) ([1997] 2 FLR 426, at [30]).

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

  • Anderson, J. 2014. Autonomy and vulnerability entwined. In Vulnerability: New essays in ethics and feminist philosophy (pp , eds. C. 134 – 61), W. Mackenzie, Rogers, and S. Dodds, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Archard D. Informed consent: Autonomy and self-ownership. Journal of Applied Philosophy. 2008; 25 (1):19–34. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Beauchamp TL, Childress JF. Principles of Biomedical Ethics. 7. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2013. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Benson P. Autonomy and oppressive socialization. Social Theory and Practice. 1991; 17 :385–408. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Braver L. Heidegger. Cambridge: Polity Press; 2014. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Buss, S., and A. Westlund. 2018. Personal autonomy. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy , E. N. Zalta (ed). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/personal-autonomy/ . Accessed February 28, 2020.
  • Christman J. The politics of persons: Individual autonomy and socio-historical selves. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2009. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Christman, J. 2004. Relational autonomy, liberal individualism and the social constitution of selves. Philosophical Studies 117(1/2): 143 – 64.
  • Clough B. Disability and vulnerability: Challenging the capacity/incapacity binary. Social Policy and Society. 2017; 16 (3):469–481. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Clough B. Vulnerability and capacity to consent to sex—asking the right questions. Child and Family Law Quarterly. 2014; 26 (4):371–396. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Coggon J, Miola J. Autonomy, liberty, and medical decision-making. Cambridge Law Journal. 2011; 70 (3):523–547. [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Crowell S. Normativity and phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2013. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Dodds S. Dependence, care and vulnerability. In: Mackenzie C, Rogers W, Dodds S, editors. Vulnerability: New essays in ethics and feminist philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2014. pp. 181–203. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Dreyfus H. Heidegger’s critique of the Husserl/Searle account of intentionality. In: Wrathall M, editor. Skillful coping: Essays on the phenomenology of everyday perception and action. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2014. pp. 76–91. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Dreyfus, H. 2000. A Merleau-Pontyian critique of Husserl’s and Searle’s representationalist accounts of action. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100(3): 287–302.
  • Foddy, B., and J. Savulescu. 2006. Addiction and autonomy: Can addicted people consent to the prescription of their drug of addiction? Bioethics 20 (1): 1–15. [ PubMed ]
  • Friedman M. Autonomy, gender, politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2003. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Gabbay E, McCarthy MW, Fins JJ. The care of the ultra-orthodox Jewish patient. Journal of Religion and Health. 2017; 56 (2):545–560. [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Gallagher S. Phenomenology. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan; 2012. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Glick S, Jotkowitz A, Prager K, Schwartz G, Twerski A, Weiss B. Responses to ‘A proposal to improve Rabbinic decision-making for serious medical problems. ’ Hakirah The Flatbush Journal of Jewish Law and Thought. 2011; 11 :211–223. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Heidegger M. Gesamtausgabe. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann; 1975. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Herring J, Wall J. Autonomy, capacity and vulnerable adults: Filling the gaps in the Mental Capacity Act. Legal Studies. 2015; 35 (4):698–719. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Holroyd, J. 2009. Relational autonomy and paternalistic interventions. Res Publica 15 (4): 321–336.
  • Humpston C, Broome M. Thinking, believing, and hallucinating self in schizophrenia. Lancet Psychiatry. 2020; 7 (7):638–646. doi: 10.1016/S2215-0366(20)30007-9. [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Husserl, E. 2001. Logical investigations . 2 vols. J. N. Findlay (trans). London: Routledge.
  • Husserl, E. 1982. Ideas Pertaining to A Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy, First Book: General Introduction to a Pure Phenomenology . F. Kersten (trans). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Kapp S, Steward R, Crane L, Elliott D, Elphick C, Pellicano E, Russell G. ‘People should be allowed to do what they like’: Autistic adults’ views and experiences of stimming. Autism. 2019; 23 (7):1782–1792. [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Kong C. Mental capacity in relationship: Decision-making, dialogue, and autonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2017. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Lewis J. Autonomy and the limits of cognitive enhancement. Bioethics. 2021; 35 (1):15–22. [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Lewis J. Safeguarding vulnerable autonomy? Situational vulnerability, the inherent jurisdiction and insights from feminist philosophy. Medical Law Review. 2021; 29 (2):306–336. [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Lewis J. Getting obligations right: Autonomy and shared decision making. Journal of Applied Philosophy. 2020; 37 (1):118–140. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Mackenzie C. Relational Autonomy. In: Hall KQ, Asta, editors. The Oxford handbook of feminist philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2021. pp. 374–384. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Mackenzie C. Responding to the agency dilemma: Autonomy, adaptive preferences, and internalized oppression. In: Oshana M, editor. Personal autonomy and social oppression. London: Routledge; 2015. pp. 48–67. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Mackenzie C. The importance of relational autonomy and capabilities for an ethics of vulnerability. In: Mackenzie C, Rogers W, Dodds S, editors. Vulnerability: New essays in ethics and feminist philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2014. pp. 33–59. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Mackenzie C. Relational autonomy, normative authority and perfectionism. Journal of Social Philosophy. 2008; 39 (4):512–533. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Mackenzie C, Stoljar N. Autonomy refigured. In: Mackenzie C, Stoljar N, editors. Relational autonomy: Feminist perspectives on autonomy, agency and the social self. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2000. pp. 3–31. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Mackenzie C, Rogers W, Dodds S. What is vulnerability and why does it matter for moral theory? In: Mackenzie C, Rogers W, Dodds S, editors. Vulnerability: New essays in ethics and feminist philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2014. pp. 1–29. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Martin W, Hickerson R. Mental capacity and the applied phenomenology of judgement. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. 2013; 12 :195–214. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Merleau-Ponty M. In: Phenomenology of perception. Smith C, editor. London: Routledge; 2002. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Meyers D. Decentralizing autonomy: Five faces of selfhood. In: Christman J, Anderson J, editors. Autonomy and the challenges to liberalism: New essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2005. pp. 27–55. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Meyers D. Intersectional identity and the authentic self? Opposites attract! In: Mackenzie C, Stoljar N, editors. Relational autonomy: Feminist perspectives on autonomy, agency and the social self. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2000. pp. 151–180. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Meyers D. Self, society, and personal choice. New York: Columbia University Press; 1989. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Meynen G. Depression, possibilities, and competence: A phenomenological perspective. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics. 2011; 32 (3):181–191. [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Oshana M. Personal autonomy and society. Journal of Social Philosophy. 1998; 29 (1):81–102. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Schaefer GO, Kahane G, Savulescu J. Autonomy and enhancement. Neuroethics. 2014; 7 :123–136. [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Sheehan T. Making sense of Heidegger: A paradigm shift. London and New York: Rowman Littlefield; 2014. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Smith J. Merleau-Ponty and the phenomenological reduction. Inquiry. 2005; 48 (6):553–571. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Svenaeus F. Das unheimliche – Towards a phenomenology of illness. Medicine Health Care and Philosophy. 2000; 3 (1):3–16. [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Svenaeus F. The body uncanny — Further steps towards a phenomenology of illness. Medicine Health Care and Philosophy. 2000; 3 (2):125–137. [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Walker T. Respecting autonomy without disclosing information. Bioethics. 2013; 27 :388–389. [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Westlund A. Relational autonomy and practical authority. In: Garavaso P, editor. The Bloomsbury companion to analytic feminism (pp. 375 – 93) London: Bloomsbury; 2018. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Westlund A. Rethinking relational autonomy. Hypatia. 2009; 24 :26–49. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Wrathall M. Autonomy, authenticity, and the self. In: McManus D, editor. Heidegger, authenticity and the self. London: Routledge; 2015. pp. 193–214. [ Google Scholar ]
  • KSAT Insider
  • KSAT Connect
  • Entertainment

What would Lisa Simpson do? NYU student protesters asked to ponder ethical issues

Karen Matthews

Associated Press

Copyright 2024 The Associated Press. All rights reserved

FILE - New York University students and pro-Palestinian supporters rally outside the NYU Stern School of Business building, Monday, April 22, 2024, in New York. Some NYU students facing discipline for their actions during this spring's pro-Palestinian protests have been assigned a 49-page workbook that includes a "Simpsons"-based module on ethical decision making. Some have been asked to write an apologetic "reflection paper" and submit it "in 12-point Times New Roman or similar font."(AP Photo/Mary Altaffer, File)

NEW YORK – Would Lisa Simpson set up a tent at New York University to protest the war in Gaza? How would Principal Skinner respond if she did?

Hard to say, but some NYU students facing discipline for their actions during this spring's pro-Palestinian protests have been assigned a 49-page workbook that includes a “Simpsons”-based module on ethical decision-making. Some have been asked to write an apologetic “reflection paper” and submit it “in 12-point Times New Roman or similar font.”

Recommended Videos

Like colleges across the U.S., NYU was the scene of protests over Israel's response to the Oct. 7 Hamas attack during the last weeks of the spring semester.

More than 100 NYU students were arrested when police cleared an encampment at the university's Manhattan campus on April 22, and about a dozen more were arrested at a smaller encampment on May 3.

NYU's school year has ended, but the university is requiring some student protesters to go through a disciplinary process that includes answering questions like “What are your values? Did the decision you made align with your personal values?” in a double-spaced reflection paper.

Others must complete a 49-page “Ethos Integrity Series” that asks students to rank their values from 1 to 42 and complete assignments like “write about how your values affect your daily life and the decisions you make.”

One section is based on an episode of “The Simpsons” in which Lisa uncharacteristically cheats on a test and is wracked by guilt. Principal Skinner, meanwhile, wants to keep the cheating under wraps so the school can get a grant. Questions in the ethics workbook include “What, if anything, could Lisa have done or thought about to make better decisions?” and “What are the potential and actual consequences of Principal Skinner’s decisions?”

An NYU group called Faculty & Staff for Justice in Palestine criticized the assignments in a news release.

Sara Pursley, an associate professor of Middle Eastern and Islamic Studies, noted that students completing the reflection paper are told they must not try to justify their actions or “challenge a conduct regulation.”

“Since they can’t write anything justifying their action, students seem to be banned from writing about personal values that might be relevant here, such as a belief in freedom of expression, the responsibility to oppose genocide, or the duty of nonviolent civil disobedience under certain circumstances," Pursley said. "This seems rather ironic in an essay on integrity.”

NYU spokesperson John Beckman said the disciplinary process is meant to be educational.

“The point of these essays is to reflect upon how a student’s way of expressing their values might be having an impact on other members of the NYU community,” Beckman said. “We think that’s a worthwhile goal.”

He added, “Which is not to say that the specific assignments couldn’t be improved."

Faculty members and staff from NYU's Office of Student Conduct will meet in the fall, Beckman said, to consider “what might be done to improve the quality of the prompts for the reflection papers as well as the other educational assignments."

Copyright 2024 The Associated Press. All rights reserved. This material may not be published, broadcast, rewritten or redistributed without permission.

IMAGES

  1. 50 Best Reflective Essay Examples (+Topic Samples) ᐅ TemplateLab

    reflective essay on clinical decision making

  2. Clinical Reflective Journal (300 Words)

    reflective essay on clinical decision making

  3. Examples of reflective writing in nursing using gibbs. examples of

    reflective essay on clinical decision making

  4. 50 Best Reflective Essay Examples (+Topic Samples) ᐅ TemplateLab

    reflective essay on clinical decision making

  5. Clinical Reflective Essay

    reflective essay on clinical decision making

  6. 50 Best Reflective Essay Examples (+Topic Samples) ᐅ TemplateLab

    reflective essay on clinical decision making

VIDEO

  1. critical reflective essay- Apurav maggu

  2. Reflective Essay Topic Ideas

  3. CLINICAL DECISION MAKING. Announcement

  4. Reflective practice with Clinical Excellence Commission Chief Executive Prof Michael Nicholl

  5. Clinical Trials and Intellectual Property Rights

  6. #what is Reflective essay? #english #ytshorts #viral #shorts #jyotigupta English teacher

COMMENTS

  1. Reflective Essay on Clinical Decision Making

    Reflective Essay on Clinical Decision Making. Clinical decision making in nursing involves applying critical thinking skills to select the best available evidence based option to control risks and address patients' needs in the provision of high quality care that nurses are accountable for. - Standing, M. (2011)

  2. Deliberate reflection and clinical reasoning: Founding ideas and

    The present essay aims to help clarify the role of deliberate reflection in diagnostic reasoning. ... Prakash et al. 3 were only able to find 23 studies in which the influence of reflection on clinical decision making was conducted with sufficient ... From mindless to mindful practice—cognitive bias and clinical decision making. N Engl J Med ...

  3. Decision-Making in Nursing Practice: An Integrative Literature Review

    Ideal nurse decision-making is essential to enhanced patient care outcomes. This review identified numerous complex influences in the nurse decision-making process. Decision-making in clinical nursing requires a multifaceted approach to research, education, and practice to ensure best outcomes.

  4. Reflective practice in health care and how to reflect effectively

    Introduction. Reflective practice is something most people first formally encounter at university. This may be reflecting on a patient case, or an elective, or other experience. However, what you may not have considered is that you have been subconsciously reflecting your whole life: thinking about and learning from past experiences to avoid ...

  5. Structured reflection on shared decision making

    INTRODUCTION. Shared decision making (SDM) is 'a process in which clinicians and patients work together to select tests, treatments, management or support packages based on patients' informed preferences' and the best available evidence. 1 SDM, a key factor in enhancing patient safety and quality of care, can reduce prescribing errors and improve medicines adherence, 2 and is ...

  6. Clinical Decision Making

    When considering theories of clinical decision making it is important to reflect on where our knowledge and information come from. The Delphi technique allows many people to contribute to the decision-making process and it may reduce the dialogue and chatter or even conflict between members of a larger group. Groups bring more complete ...

  7. Integrating patient management, reflective practice, and ethical

    Background Integration of clinical skills, ethical decision-making, and reflection skills have emerged as cornerstones of clinical teaching in medical schools. This study aimed to detect whether a multimodal learning environment approach consisting of lectures, a drill, post-drill video debriefing, and written reflection in an emergency medicine rotation boot camp improves interns' patient ...

  8. Effective decision-making: applying the theories to nursing practice

    Consequently, the following assessment and decision-making processes were conducted within the remits of practice as a student nurse. Decision-making is a dynamic process in nursing practice, and the theories emphasise the importance of adaptability and reflective practice to identify factors that impact on patient care (Pearson, 2013). Three ...

  9. Clinical reflective practice

    Introduction. Reflective practice is an established component of medical education and clinical development. It is accepted that the process of critically reflecting on a clinical experience enhances knowledge and understanding, and facilitates learning. 1 Experiences, good and bad, provide learning opportunities for the individuals involved and for the wider system.

  10. The importance of the user voice in clinical decision making: a

    The context of decision-making theory is a large one, with a range of different theories and models. These can be broadly categorised as normative, descriptive or prescriptive (Bell et al, 1995), or those looking at optimised decision making, recommendations to improve decision making, and descriptions of decision making processes (Standing ...

  11. Effects of reflection on clinical decision-making of intensive care

    Conclusion. Reflection could improve the clinical decision-making of ICU nurses. It is, thus, recommended to incorporate this method into the nursing curriculum and care practices. •. Clinical decision-making is a fundamental concept in the field of nursing which affects the course of patient care and recovery. •.

  12. Reflective Essay on Clinical Decision Making

    Reflective Essay on Clinical Decision Making. Clinical decision making in nursing involves applying critical thinking skills to select the best available evidence based option to control risks and address patients' needs in the provision of high quality care that nurses are accountable for. - Standing, M. (2011)

  13. Using clinical decision making and reflection strategies to support

    Clinical decision making has been studied in medicine over the last few decades (Norman, 2005). Jensen et al (2009) noted that very little evaluation has been conducted in the paramedic population. This article highlights the need for the study of clinical decision making which forms a vital part of the paramedic's practice.

  14. Comparative Theories in Clinical Decision Making and their Application

    The author's experience of clinical decision making details the diagnosis of an acute myocardial infarction and the decision-making process taken to reach this. To maintain confidentiality, the identity of the patient, hospital and other healthcare professionals have been anonymised in accordance with the Nursing and Midwifery Council's (NMC ...

  15. Rethinking clinical decision-making to improve clinical reasoning

    Go to: Improving clinical reasoning techniques is the right way to facilitate decision-making from prognostic, diagnostic, and therapeutic points of view. However, the process to do that is to fill knowledge gaps by studying and growing experience and knowing some cognitive aspects to raise the awareness of thinking mechanisms to avoid ...

  16. Reflective practice in clinical psychology: Reflections from basic

    Despite their widespread adoption, reflective practice techniques are largely lacking in supportive outcome evidence. We contend that the reflective practice literature has remained largely disconnected from basic psychological science, especially work on the limitations of (a) introspection as a means of becoming aware of one's biases, (b ...

  17. The use of reflection in midwifery practice to inform clinical decision

    The mean and standard deviation of the age of the subjects was 21.24 ± 1.83. 61.4% of the participants had the moderate Decision-Making ability, and 38.6% of them had high Decision-Making ability ...

  18. Undergraduate mental health nursing students' reflections in gaining

    This study incorporates the theoretical position that reflecting on practice and the development of skills can synthesise both 'classroom' and clinical knowledge (Naber and Markley, 2017). The pedagogic approach to this research uses student reflective essays to examine acquired understanding and skills in the critical appraisal of research.

  19. Clinical decision-making in complex healthcare delivery systems

    Situation. Clinical decision-making is a complex process involving information processing, evaluation of evidence, and application of relevant knowledge to select the appropriate interventions that provide high-quality care and reduce risk of patient harm (Standing, 2007).Decision-making can range from fast, intuitive, or heuristic to carefully reasoned, analytical, or evidence-based.

  20. A nursing student's reflective account of decision-making in a ...

    Squirrell B, Hunt J (2018) A nursing student's reflective account of decision-making in a school nursing setting. Nursing Children and Young People. doi: 10.7748/ncyp.2018.e1012. This article has been subject to open peer review and has been checked for plagiarism using automated software. [email protected]. None declared.

  21. Advanced practice: critical thinking and clinical reasoning

    As detailed in the table, multiple themes surrounding the cognitive and meta-cognitive processes that underpin clinical reasoning have been identified. Central to these processes is the practice of critical thinking. Much like the definition of clinical reasoning, there is also diversity with regard to definitions and conceptualisation of critical thinking in the healthcare setting.

  22. Cognitive bias during clinical decision-making and its influence on

    Background: An integral part of clinical practice is decision-making. Yet there is widespread acceptance that there is evidence of cognitive bias within clinical practice among nurses and physicians. However, how cognitive bias among emergency nurses and physicians' decision-making influences patient outcomes remains unclear.

  23. Patient autonomy, clinical decision making, and the Phenomenological

    Phenomenological Reduction: Towards a Functional Definition. Before we explore the implications of the phenomenological reduction for clinical decision making and the relationships between a more phenomenologically oriented conception of autonomy and traditional theories of autonomy, we need to understand what the phenomenological reduction is and how it intervenes on questions of ...

  24. What would Lisa Simpson do? NYU student protesters asked to ponder

    "The point of these essays is to reflect upon how a student's way of expressing their values might be having an impact on other members of the NYU community," Beckman said. "We think that ...