Trinity College Law Review (TCLR) | Trinity College Dublin

A Critical Analysis of the Criminalisation of Omissions

Samuel carthy.

Introduction

This essay aims to critically analyse the place of omissions within the criminal law, which traditionally has primarily focused on acts of commission which result in harm to another. However, in certain circumstances, it can penalise an act of omission, which is ‘something which is not done in circumstances where there is some reason or expectation for that thing to be done’. [1] This essay aims to assess the circumstances where such an expectation is held by the justice system. The common law generally imposes such a duty to act in four specific circumstances: where the defendant is a public servant, has a familial relationship to the victim, voluntarily assumed responsibility for the victim or created the danger to the victim. [2] In all other circumstances, there is generally no duty to act, even when it would be morally reprehensible to fail to do so. For example, an able-bodied person who does not attempt to save a drowning baby is not a murderer in the eyes of the law.  In some other jurisdictions, attempts have been made to impose a duty to help others in the form of ‘Good Samaritan’ laws.  This essay will also examine their application in continental jurisdictions.

Familial Relationship

As mentioned above, there are limited circumstances where criminal law imposes a duty to act. Perhaps the most obvious of these is when there is a familial relationship between parties. One of the earlier examples of this is R v Senior, [3] where a father was found guilty of manslaughter for refusing medication to treat his son’s pneumonia because of his religious beliefs. The rationale here is pragmatic. As a father, it is his fundamental duty to keep his son alive; by refusing to seek medical help, he was as responsible for his son’s death as the ailment that killed him.  This was somewhat contradicted decades later in R v Lowe, [4] when a father of low intelligence was acquitted of manslaughter. His daughter died after he failed to call a doctor; here, the rationale being that he had not foreseen the consequences of this failure. It is submitted this argument is overly cautious in its unwillingness to criminalise an omission, suggesting that parents caring for infants do not have a duty to know when to call for medical help. While this judgment was influenced by the low intelligence of both the father and the mother, surely such knowledge is a non-derogable requirement of parenthood, and as Mr Lowe had had children taken from him before,  he ought to have been even more vigilant in the circumstances.

The reverse relationship was considered in DPP v Joel, [5] where a mother with MS died whilst living in the home of her daughter and her daughter’s partner. She was poorly cared for and developed infected bedsores as a result of her condition. She contracted pneumonia and passed away after being taken to hospital for treatment. The daughter was found to have been negligent in the care of her mother, however questions raised concerning the negligence of the HSE lead to no conviction for the mother’s death. The prosecution also failed to prove that the daughter’s partner owed the mother a duty of care in this case. This particular case is interesting due to the family dynamic it encompasses. While parents have a natural responsibility to care for their underage children, there is a debate to be had on whether children have a responsibility to care for their parents, and whether that responsibility is a natural or legal one. In this case, neither the daughter nor her partner wanted the mother in their home. There is an argument to be made that the law should not impose a duty of care on them where they had no choice in the matter.

Public Service

Omissions are also penalised when the defendant is a public servant, as these people have duties to safeguard the public and their failure to do so can have very serious consequences. One harrowing Irish example is DPP v Bartley, [6] where a woman endured sexual abuse by her stepbrother for 25 years after her complaint to a Garda was ignored. The Garda was ultimately found to have failed in their duty to investigate all credible claims. The earlier case, R. v Dytham, [7] was cited as a precedent, where a police officer was convicted of misconduct in a public office for watching a man be beaten to death and not intervening. Both these cases establish the important precedent that police officers have a duty of care to all of society, and because of the high-stakes nature of their work, failing to act when they clearly should have acted can lead to criminal convictions. This ensures that they feel obliged to perform their job correctly and comprehensively and that the public receives the protection  they deserve.

Creation of Danger

One of the more abstract conditions where an individual can be held criminally liable for an omission is in a situation where they created a danger to others. In R v Miller, [8] the House of Lords found the defendant guilty of arson by omission. He had fallen asleep with a cigarette in his hand, woken up to find the mattress on fire, and instead of making an effort to put the fire out, moved to another room and allowed the building to be damaged. This established a common-sense precedent that a person who creates a danger is under a legal duty to alleviate the effects of that danger. The Court of Appeal extended this principle in R v Evans, [9] where they upheld a manslaughter conviction. The defendant had acquired heroin for her sister on which she overdosed and died, but both she and her mother did not seek medical help for fear of legal trouble. They found that an individual who contributes to a life-threatening state of affairs has a duty to take reasonable steps to save the other’s life. These rulings are not consistent with the emphasis put on autonomy and free will in criminal law, [10] but nonetheless, they are justified. In both of these cases, the defendants acted callously in failing to mitigate danger and prevent serious harm to others when they could have easily done so. In the interest of the common good, such negligent behaviour must be criminalised.

Voluntary Assumption of Duty

Perhaps the most unclear criminalisation of omissions comes in the form of voluntary assumptions of duty. In R v Gibbins and Proctor, [11] the first defendant left his wife and brought his children with him to live with the second defendant. The second defendant deprived one of his daughters of food and allowed her to starve to death, and both were ultimately convicted of murder. Even though the second defendant was not related to the deceased, she had acted as her mother and therefore owed her a duty of care. In R v Stone and Dobinson [12] the first defendant’s sister, who rented a room from him, died after living in squalor. Both he and the second defendant, his mistress-cum-housemaid, were convicted of manslaughter. As she had washed and provided food for the deceased, as well as attempted to summon a doctor, the second defendant had voluntarily assumed a duty of care. There is a grey area here regarding the liability of the second defendant. It may be argued that due to the lack of a concrete relationship between her and the deceased, as well her bona fide efforts to care for the deceased, she should not have been responsible for her death.

The principle of voluntary assumption of duty was arguably extended too far in the case of R v Taktak. [13] The defendant had brought a prostitute, who was nearly unconscious when he collected her, to his heroin dealer’s home, where he tried to help her but did not call a doctor. When the dealer arrived, he called a doctor, who pronounced the prostitute dead. It was found that the defendant had assumed a duty of care for her as, by bringing her to the dealer’s home, there was no chance of anyone else helping her. This is a tentative argument, as the defendant had no prior relationship with the woman. It is predicated on the assumption that, had he not collected her, a passer-by would have gotten medical assistance for her. This is a worryingly broad interpretation of a voluntary assumption of duty to a stranger. Will the courts one day impose the duty to call an ambulance on said passers-by? Any further extension of Taktak would be moving beyond the realm of administering justice and verging on infringing on individual liberty and autonomy.

Duty to Rescue and Duty to Act – An Alternative?

One of the proposed alternatives to this dilemma that we have seen in other jurisdictions, such as in France and Germany, is the imposition of so-called ‘Good Samaritan’ laws. These laws range from imposing a duty to rescue someone in peril to imposing a duty to act to prevent a crime. Both jurisdictions impose a ‘duty to rescue’ incurring a penalty of imprisonment or a fine. Section 323(c) of the German Criminal Code mandates assisting in the case of an accident, danger or emergency where it would not endanger oneself, while Article 223(6) of the French Penal Code requires offering assistance to a person in danger where it would not endanger oneself. It is submitted that the German laws in this area are fairer and less imposing on the general public than the French equivalents. The German duty to rescue, unlike the French, hinges on necessity in a manner analogous to the requirement for causation in the tort of negligence, as well as reasonability. Failing the French duty, on the other hand, does not require that your failure to help a person in danger actually had harmful consequences, or proof that your assistance would have been successful. [14]

Germany has an interesting approach to a ‘duty to act’. The official English translation of section 13 of the German Criminal Code sets out not a duty to act, but rather a penalty for ‘whoever fails to prevent a result which is an element of a criminal provision (...) if they are legally responsible for ensuring that the result does not occur and if the omission is equivalent to the [commission of] the offence through a positive act’. This provision is much more limited in scope than a more generic ‘duty to act’, while still achieving the desired result. It essentially imposes a duty to act only on parties with some degree of responsibility for would-be criminals. [15] More importantly, this duty is only breached should the crime actually occur, and where failing to prevent the crime is morally reprehensible enough to be equivalent to actually committing the crime oneself. [16] Opponents of these laws in other jurisdictions argue that the many nuances involved in the decision to undertake a rescue would make a failure to rescue difficult to prosecute. The potential rescuer may have only a split-second to assess their capabilities to perform a rescue and the danger they may face in doing so. [17] In any serious attempt to deal with rescuers under the law, courts would need to adopt a subjective test as to the difficulty of the rescue from the rescuer’s perspective at the time. [18]   It is submitted that the German provision here is effectual, but no more so than the current state of the common law.

Using a literal interpretation of actus reus, no omission could constitute a crime. However, the courts have correctly adopted a pragmatic, albeit cautious, approach to situations where a person’s failure to act should be considered criminal. In some of the cases mentioned above, particularly those where people have sat back and allowed their family members to die from neglect, there can be no doubt that the severity of a criminal conviction is deserved. This desire to issue just rulings must be carefully balanced with the fundamental legal principles of individual liberty and autonomy. Good morals cannot and must not be mandated by the judiciary. Legislative attempts to impose a duty to help others may be well-meaning, but to be effectual, they would have to be no more broad in scope than the current state of the common law. In Germany we have seen a more practical approach when compared to the paternalistic approach taken by France. Only those most heinous omissions should be criminalised, and even then only in situations where the person in question had a clear duty to act, be it as a result of their behaviour, their profession or their close relationship to those affected by their omission.

[1] A P Simester, ‘Why Omissions are Special’ (1995) 1 LEG 311.

[2] Conor Hanly, An Introduction to Irish Criminal Law (3rd edn, Gill & Macmillan 2015) 59.

[3] [1989] 1 QB 283.

[4] [1973] 1 QB 702.

[5] [2016] IECA 120.

[6] [1997] 6 JIC 1301.

[7] [1979] 1 QB 722.

[8] [1983] 2 AC 161.

[9] [2009] 1 WLR 1999.

[10] Hanly (n 2) 57.

[11] [1918] 13 CrAppR 134.

[12] [1977] 1 QB 354.

[13] [1988] 34 ACR 334.

[14] Andrew Ashworth and Eva Steiner, 'Criminal Omissions and Public Duties: The French Experience' (1990) 10 LS 153

[15] George P Fletcher, 'Criminal Omissions: Some Perspectives' (1976) 24 AJCL 703.

[17] Gavin Dingwall and Alisdair A Gillespie, 'Reconsidering the Good Samaritan: A Duty to Rescue' (2008) 39 Cambrian L Rev 26.

Share this:

Leave a reply cancel reply.

How Omissions Aren’t Special

  • Original Paper
  • Open access
  • Published: 16 December 2023

Cite this article

You have full access to this open access article

  • Kate Greasley 1  

616 Accesses

Explore all metrics

Avoid common mistakes on your manuscript.

1 Not-Doings and Omissions

The basic structure of the criminal law features what appears to be a stark asymmetry between the treatment of acts and omissions. Whereas we are prima facie accountable for harms that come about as a result of our positive acts, only in exceptional circumstances are we accountable for the harms which depend on our omissions. I may be liable for an omission if a distinct duty to act can be adduced, and if my failure to discharge that duty is culpable to the point of criminality (after all, positive moral obligations practically besiege us, and failing to discharge them is hardly ever seriously culpable). I have a duty to feed a child because I am her parent; Footnote 1 a duty to call the ambulance for a critically sick relative because he is in my house; Footnote 2 a duty to close a railway gate because I am the person employed to do it; Footnote 3 a duty to put out a fire, or call the fire brigade, because I am the one who started it. Footnote 4 Apart from where these exceptional duties arise, one’s decision to allow a preventable harm to occur is no business of the criminal law, on the standard picture.

This default rule is one of the very first things students of the criminal law are made to learn. Omissions, we tell them, are special. The rule is all at once intuitive and curious. Intuitive, firstly, because it is unthinkable that failures to prevent harm in general should engage the attention of the criminal law. As Simester points out early on in his incisive reappraisal of the omissions problem in Fundamentals of Criminal Law , the category of ‘not-doings’ is boundless. Footnote 5 Consider how much hardship I fail to prevent merely by not sending more money to charity, by not volunteering in my local food bank, by choosing to be an ok legal academic rather than a spectacular nurse. So much activity to prevent harm is also mutually exclusive, of course: there is only so much one can do in the context of a single life, and putting one’s efforts into harm prevention of some kinds (inasmuch as one ever does this), will necessarily come at the expense of other kinds.

These reflections show why the default rule is so natural: failure to prevent harm is an inescapable fact of life, so it cannot be a general basis for criminal answerability. But they also demonstrate the curiousness of approaching this state of affairs as a rule to be explained and defended. For what would it possibly look like for the criminal law to treat our not-doings in general on a par with our doings? It is not easy to get a handle on this proposal, so as to explain why we do not take it up. Simester sets himself the task of justifying a default rule according to which ‘we are not accountable for failing to prevent something that it would be a crime to bring about through a positive act’, Footnote 6 but only become accountable, in law, when a special duty to act can be scoped out. Why should the law not treat not-doings tout court just like it treats positive acts, he asks. Footnote 7 Completely aside, though, from questions of justice in accountability, it is not clear what it would mean to be held responsible for all the bad things I fail to prevent as if I had brought them about via a positive act. How would the law even begin to assign ‘not-doings’ under this definition, so as to apportion liability for them? The issue here is that when the focus of our investigations is the law’s default rule around ‘not-doings’, understood as all the bad states of affairs I could improve but do not, it is difficult to see what alternatives there are to argue over. Surely, some principles must be fashioned from the outset to pick out from this limitless category of events those things that can be said to be my not-doings, as opposed to yet more things that happen in the world.

This is precisely where omissions come in. Omissions are more narrowly defined than the broader category of not-doings. An omission is the thing I didn’t do which I clearly had a duty to do, which, in the ordinary course of things, I would do, and, or, which any decent person in my position would have done. These features of omissions are critical to our ability to detect them amidst the sprawling ether of events one’s interventions could have affected. Omissions are, in this respect, like the hole in a donut, only hoving into view when viewed against the surrounding context which gives them their shape and defines their very existence. In this vein, Simester notes that omissions are a special subset of not-doings of a ‘morally significant kind’. Footnote 8 To say ‘You omitted to X’ is invariably to say something in the accusatory mood.

This makes a certain kind of sense of Simester’s decision to set his analytical sights on a default rule about not-doings rather than about omissions. Why treat not-doings differently from positive acts is the question to answer, he suggests. Are they, ceteris paribus, less culpable than our doings? Are they not causes of harm in the same way our positive acts are? Does liability for not-doings restrict our liberty in a special way? The question cannot be ‘Why treat omissions differently?’, is the thinking, because omissions are the subset of not-doings for which we are, almost by definition, answerable in some way. In their legal instantiation, omissions therefore constitute the exception to the default rule that we are not liable for our not-doings. The default rule pertains to the not-doings, not to the omissions.

But outside of the clutch of principles that define omissions, which bring them into view and give them their shape, there is no basis on which we can designate my not-doings and distinguish them from the not-doings of others. Outwith these principles, whatever they may be, there is no given set of not-doings yoked to each one us that present as candidate criminal offences. Defined as all the ills we fail to prevent, the category is far too vast, unruly, and full of internal tensions to provide such candidates. This is all to say, we can start only with omissions—with the things we fail to do that have normative salience, that stand in defiance of some expectation, moral or social (or both). The default rules worth exploring, I therefore maintain—the rules that present liability options the law could conceivably pursue—are those which concern the law’s approach to responsibility for our omissions, for those failures to act which stand out as our very own not-doings.

2 Ascribing Responsibility through Acts and Omissions

Is there a special default rule that applies to omissions ? I want to suggest that once we have the category omissions in our grasp, so to speak, it is far less clear that a special default rule exists with respect to it. A candidate default rule, transposing from Simester’s description of the rule about not-doings, is that whereas we are generally answerable in law for our harmful positive acts, we are not, generally, answerable for our harmful omissions. To reiterate, I am defining omissions as those of our inactions that in some way defy normative expectations.

Thinking about not-doings, Simester suggests that a default no-liability rule can be justified by reference to a few principled considerations. Most prominent of these is what he calls ‘the range-of-alternatives distinction’. Footnote 9 The core idea here is that when the law prohibits inaction, thus mandating conduct , it blocks us from engaging in our own projects and commitments while the positive duty is being fulfilled. This is not true when the law prohibits harmful positive acts. Each such prohibition knocks out only one option, but leaves the full range of other activities available. But this is not the only justification for the law’s forbearance, Simester argues. He also claims that not-doings are also typically less culpable than are their counterpart positive acts, and that the law ought to reflect this through the default rule. Finally, he argues that a person is prima facie not accountable for her not-doings, whereas she is for her doings.

Tuning into these considerations explains why we are generally not liable for our failures to prevent harm, Simester suggests, and why, therefore, a distinct duty to act, rooted in some kind of connection to the harm, is needed to legitimate legal answerability. But I have said that failures to act in breach of some distinct duty—what we should call ‘omissions’—are the only real candidates for any default rules about liability. To return to my own question, then, could considerations of the same kinds explain and justify the general no-liability rule which applies to omissions but not to positive acts? The main comment I wish to field in response to this question is that I am unconvinced there is a special ‘no liability’ rule that applies distinctly to omissions and not to positive acts.

We have already seen that any account of omissions requires us to carve out from the unlimited class of bad things I fail to prevent those which can credibly count as my non-deeds. Notice, however, that matters are very similar in respect of our deeds as well. We are not automatically accountable, even prima facie, for all of the ills that are causally connected to our movements in the world. What makes it the case, then, that X was something I did , was my harmful positive act, as opposed to one of the unlimited events which are causally dependent on my behaviour? In the words of Donald Davidson:

What events in the life of a person reveal agency; what are his deeds and doings in contrast to mere happenings in his history; what is the mark that distinguishes his actions? Footnote 10

Out of the morass of ‘mere happenings’, the law is compelled to define the realm of our positive acts through principles of ascriptive responsibility that tie various happenings to our agency. It is only by reference to such principles that we are able to say, for instance, that wounding Jim is something the defendant did , rather than something that simply occurred after the defendant moved his body this way or that with a knife.

The criminal law doles out and delimits ascriptive responsibility for positive acts in large part through its doctrines of causation and remoteness, and, in particular, through the insufficiency of ‘but for’ causation for establishing legal causation. The law’s doctrines of causation do not ask only whether the defendant’s conduct was a sine qua non of the relevant harm. They insist, also, on a requisite degree of directness between conduct and harm, on the absence of ‘intervening’ causes, and, arguably, on some out of the ordinary, sub-optimal, or duty-breaching character of the behaviour which sets the harm in motion. Footnote 11

In R v Kennedy (2007), the defendant filled a syringe with heroin and handed it over to the victim, who injected himself with the drug and consequently died of an overdose. Footnote 12 The pertinent legal question, on appeal, was whether the defendant had really caused the victim’s death, so as to be guilty of unlawful act manslaughter. It was held on appeal that the victim’s voluntary act of self-injecting was an intervening cause. Killing the victim was not something the defendant did, therefore, though his actions were a link in the causal chain leading to the victim’s death. As in so many cases, we see, in Kennedy , the doctrines of legal causation being used to sift out our responsible deeds from the unlimited bad states of affairs that depend on what we do. Given the victim’s intervention, killing the victim could not count as among the defendant’s deeds, though it was a downstream effect of his actions.

It is instructive to consider Kennedy alongside R v Evans , another heroin overdose case. Footnote 13 There, the defendant witnessed her sister dying, over the course of a night, from an overdose of drugs that the defendant had supplied to her, failing to call the ambulance until it was too late. The court ruled that the defendant owed her sister a duty of care, having created the dangerous situation she watched unfold. The breach of this duty (through not calling the ambulance soon enough) established her guilt for gross negligence manslaughter. The omission made it the case that her sister’s death was attributable to her.

From a certain point of view, Kennedy and Evans approached the same question from different sides. There is a baseline rule, let us say, that one is not responsible for the heroin-related deaths of others, in general, and even where they are causally dependent on something one does, such as supplying the heroin. Supplying is not sufficient for the death to be ascribed to one’s agency, we might say. Exceptionally, things may stand otherwise. In the first place, they will stand otherwise if one’s causal contribution is direct enough: if the defendant in Kennedy had literally injected the victim himself, said the court. In the second place, they will stand otherwise if, having supplied the heroin, the defendant breached a clear duty to help the victim, thereby omitting to save her. Both the ‘act doctrine’ and the ‘omissions doctrine’ are means of overturning the presumption that one does not bear ascriptive responsibility for other peoples’ overdoses.

We are not, in general, criminally answerable for our non-deeds, the standard view says. But we are not, in general, criminally answerable for our deeds either, if these are understood to be all the harmed states that result from our bodily movements and presence in the world. Principles of ascriptive responsibility are equally needed to carve out one’s own definable deeds from the heap of events connected to one’s activities (was killing the victim something Kennedy did?). On this plane, there is no special rule applying to omissions that doesn’t apply to acts. The criminal acts and omissions recognised by law are alternative routes to ascribing responsibility to agents for certain consequences and distinguishing those consequences from mere happenings and events. Both doctrines, we might say, fulfil the function of delimiting the states of affairs for which we are answerable, against the more basic master rule that we are not answerable in general for harms which depend, causally or counterfactually, on how we conduct ourselves.

Seen this way, there is no special default rule that I am not answerable for my omissions. I am not answerable tout court for bad happenings, but specifying an omission runs parallel to specifying an act as a means of connecting my agency to some of those happenings. In this fairly significant way, omissions are not all that special.

3 The Lesser Culpability Claim

I have suggested that the rules about omissions liability are not as distinctive and special as might first appear, once we see them as mirror principles of ascriptive responsibility that also apply to acts. But this still leaves us with plenty of interesting things to ask about the scope of criminal liability for omissions. Should the law still exercise special restraint when it comes to imposing criminal liability for our omissions, understood as our definable, duty-breaching, not-doings? Ought we to be punished less harshly for an omission than for its equivalent positive act? Should we be criminally liable for far fewer of our harmful omissions than of our harmful positive acts?

Simester surveys three possible justifications for treating omissions (‘not-doings’, in his rendering) and acts on a different footing. These are:

1. That culpable omissions are only non-interventions, or failures to improve matters, whereas positive acts worsen states of affairs;

2. That those guilty of omissions are, all other things being equal, less culpable than those guilty of harmful positive acts; and.

3. That there is, in general, a greater loss of liberty occasioned when proscribing omissions than when proscribing acts.

For reasons of space, I will neglect point 1: whether the difference between worsening and not making better justifies the special treatment of omissions. I will confine myself instead to some remarks about points 2 and 3: the putative lesser culpability of omissions and what Simester calls ‘the range-of-alternatives’ distinction.

First, the lesser culpability claim. Are omissions, ceteris paribus, less culpable than positive acts? Doubtless, plenty of omissions are more culpable than plenty of positive acts. Watching a small child drown, a child whom you could easily save, but out of sheer indifference do not, is arguably more monstrous than the impassioned revenge killing of a loved one’s abuser. Omitting to feed one’s children, knowing they will starve, is leagues more culpable than minor assault (even of them). But these are not the right test cases for determining whether the act/omission distinction is morally neutral, because across these paired cases all things are far from equal: the degree of ultimate harm, and, in the first pair, the motives, are deeply asymmetrical.

A more promising pair of cases for testing the neutrality thesis (the thesis that, when all things are equal, it is not morally consequential whether one hurts through act or omission), as Simester indeed notes, is that of the parent who intentionally starves his child considered against the parent who outright poisons her. Footnote 14 Here, the act and omission strike us as equally murderous, never mind precisely how the parent brings about the child’s death. That suggests the moral neutrality of the act/omission distinction reveals itself just as soon as we have the right cases to see it. But that conclusion is thrown into doubt when we consider a further pair of cases. The first features the aforementioned moral degenerate who refuses to rescue a drowning child who is unknown to him, when he could easily do so at practically no cost to himself. The other features a moral degenerate who actually drowns an unknown child. Footnote 15 In this pair of cases too, it seems we have kept everything equal—as equal as they can be—and yet it yields the contrary conclusion. When all that is left between the cases is the act/omission distinction, this does indeed seem to make a considerable moral difference. Even if the person who fails to save the child from drowning is culpable to the point of criminality, he is surely not as culpable as the person who does the drowning.

These pairs of cases point us in opposite directions vis-à-vis the neutrality thesis, generating something of a puzzle, as Simester points out. But we may wonder whether even these examples succeed in maintaining the ceteris paribus proviso. In order to serve as test cases for the neutrality thesis, the presumption across all four examples is, I think, that the agents (the negligent parent; the killer parent; the indifferent stranger; the killer stranger) act or fail to act with the same intention or motive: a desire or willingness for the victim to die. To achieve this, we might suppose, for instance, that the person who fails to rescue the child from the water wishes the child’s death every bit as much as the person who positively drowns the child. This would be a very non-standard omission. But positing a symmetrical desire that the victim dies may not yet settle it that the mens rea is fixed across the cases. For, is the intent to end a person’s life by one’s own hand, by putting one’s agency in the world to work to ensure that outcome, ever the same state of mind as that which is involved in the most determined refusal to save? The killer who drowns the child intends that the outcome be brought about by his own agency; he intends, himself, to be the agent of death; the omitter intends to do nothing, and so to allow death. Are these morally equal intentions?

If, as I suspect, they are not, one might take this to upend the ceteris paribus proviso in these cases, diminishing their usefulness for pronouncing on the neutrality thesis. Contrariwise, one might argue that the persistence of some moral difference, captured by a difference in intention, is what falsifies the neutrality thesis. Perhaps what we understand to be a difference in intent constitutes the moral difference between act and omission when all else is equal.

For Simester, the great difficulty in crafting ceteris paribus examples has pointed implications. Defenders of the neutrality thesis tend to make their examples quite extraordinary, he says, ‘in order to achieve ceteris paribus terms’. Footnote 16 The hardship of achieving those terms alerts us to an important fact: ‘virtually always’, he says, omissions will be less culpable than positive acts, because things are so rarely all equal. The fact that ceteris paribus does ‘not normally hold’ hence works to justify the default rule that we are not accountable for our not-doings, but only become so where there is a distinct duty to act and a special connection to the harm.

Even if the neutrality thesis is right, then, the typical lesser culpability of not-doings gives the law a reason to ‘exclude liability’ for them as a baseline rule, Simester argues. Footnote 17 This said, the correctness of the moral neutrality thesis is attested to by the comparison of the parent who starves or poisons his child, he thinks, where it seems there really is no moral difference, as well as by numerous instances of inadvertent negligence. When D fails to take reasonable care, resulting in harm, it seems to matter precious little whether her negligence takes the form of an act or omission—whether a factory safety technician negligently fails to flip a safety switch needed to prevent accidents, or flicks off the safety switch, mistakenly thinking she was turning it on. Footnote 18

Let me venture just a few comments about these suggestions. First, the case of the parent who starves his child, along with so many examples of negligence, is indeed where the moral neutrality thesis looks at its strongest. Yet these are also the failures to prevent harm which most lend themselves to re-description as a form of conduct, or, rather, of misconduct. The parent who starves his child is not doing nothing; he is engaged in an activity, the activity of negligent child-rearing. Manifold negligent ‘omissions’ can be just as well understood in similar terms—as, rather, illicit ways of carrying on. The ‘omission’ by an anaesthetist to notice and respond to a patient’s disconnected oxygen pipe is also, and every bit as much, the activity of medical malpractice. Footnote 19 Where omissions seem the most morally equivalent to acts, then, is also where they least resemble mere inaction and are akin to the act of doing something badly, like a misreading or a misdirecting.

Does this feature of negligence cases reinforce their bearing out of the neutrality thesis, or does it instead suggest they are not the right examples with which to test it? I find it difficult to say. The characteristics that place these so-called omissions on a par with acts culpability-wise are the same characteristics which undercut their description as being, strictly speaking, omissions. The fact that omissions liability is most straightforward where omissions are at their most act-like—when they are, seen from the other end, badly performed activities Footnote 20 —also bolsters the thought that the omissions rules are, to begin with, not all that special. So much of what we might think of as liability for negligent ‘omissions’ fits neatly within a principle of prima facie accountability for one’s harmful conduct, which Simester’s remarks about inadvertent negligence helpfully illuminate. To be sure, the lazy bystander case, wherein the wrongdoer does wrong by really doing nothing (watching the saveable child drown, for instance), stands out in sharp contradistinction to these negligent performance cases, and it is no coincidence that it generates more consternation regarding criminal liability.

Second, let us return to Simester’s proposal that the typical lesser culpability of omissions part grounds the default rule that we are not legally accountable for them. Though it may be true that omissions are equally culpable when all things really are equal, this is so rarely the case that we ought not to be accountable for our failures to prevent harm unless a distinct duty to act is apparent, the suggestion goes. I have suggested that we can only get hold of our omissions, to begin with, in the light of distinct and specific duties to act. Let us assume, then, that one can almost never find positive act counterparts for these omissions, because things are almost never (if ever?) equal between omission and act. Does that sponsor the conclusion that omissions are ‘typically’ less culpable than acts? But which omissions have been adjudged less culpable than which acts, so as to reach the conclusion about typicality? Omissions in general cannot be said to be less culpable than acts in general ; it all depends which omissions and acts one has in mind, as I have said. (Refusing to call an ambulance for your critically ill mother isn’t less culpable than stealing money from your sister.) So the claim that omissions are typically ‘less culpable’ can only mean that they are typically less culpable than their counterpart positive acts . But if the ceteris paribus proviso almost never holds, we lack sufficient comparisons with direct counterparts to yield the conclusion about typically lesser culpability. To be able to say that, we actually do need to have a spread of cases where we are confident enough that all things are equal, and where it is clear the omissions are standardly less culpable. The fact that it is fiendishly difficult to find a pair of cases where all things are equal does not mean, then, that omissions are typically less culpable than positive acts.

If it turns out that in the only ceteris paribus examples we can manage to think up the omission is less culpable, this will indeed be bad news for the neutrality thesis. But disproving the neutrality thesis would not, in any case, entail that harmful omissions are typically or generally less culpable than harmful positive acts, only that every omission is less culpable than its exact positive act equivalent.

Third, and last, what sort of default rules do these reflections sponsor? Simester is quite aware of the points raised here, I believe. Given this, I propose we can faithfully restate his core claim as follows: to the extent we ever can specify a positive act that is the mirror opposite of some culpable omission, the omission will reveal itself to be less wrongful. This suggests that qua omission, there is what we might call a ‘culpability deduction’. If that were right, should the law exhibit any special reticence to criminalise omissions on this count? Footnote 21 I do not see why. Plenty of omissions are culpable enough for criminalisation even if they are not culpable on a par with their counterpart positive act, assuming we can specify one. And many omissions are much more culpable than numerous, harmful positive acts that are apt for criminalisation. Formulated this way, then, the lesser culpability claim does not endorse a principle of special legal restraint with regard to omissions qua omissions.

4 The Range-of-Alternatives Distinction

Let me now turn to the ‘range-of-alternatives distinction’. Footnote 22 Summarised above, this is the idea that prohibitions on not-doings are more onerous, in their very nature, than prohibitions on doings. In proscribing a doing, the law rules out for us only one option, whereas when mandating positive action it rules out everything else, for as long as the positive duty lives. A key plank here is the thought that we may legitimately demonstrate partiality towards our own projects, goals, and attachments as we go about our lives. Sweeping liability for failures to prevent harms to which we are not personally, uniquely connected would threaten this freedom to pursue our own ends, by demanding that we subordinate our own projects to the impersonal goal of harm prevention wherever doing so would yield results. This opportunity costs dimension is a foremost justification, as Simester sees it, for the rule that, absent a distinct duty to act, we are not accountable for not-doings.

To reiterate, I find it very difficult to conceive of a general ground of liability for not-doings prior to some principles of ascriptive responsibility that scope out what properly counts as my not-doings (as opposed to mere happenings), principles that will surely cite personal connection to particular harms, and clear and distinct duties to act. I am in full agreement with Simester that a regulatory scheme of general liability for preventable harms would seriously imperil the ability to pursue one’s own life projects. But I also find all thought of such a regulatory scheme confounding, insofar as it posits a definable category of ‘not-doings’ that does not depend on the distinct, individualised, duties to act which give omissions their shape. In a similar train to the above, then, I would rather ask whether the opportunity costs worry tends toward special restraint when it comes to criminalising omissions —the things one does not do in breach of some obvious normative expectation.

Clearly, prohibitions on positive acts can be more onerous and liberty-restricting than prohibitions on omissions. In making the ‘range of alternatives’ point, Simester asks us to ‘compare being prohibited from drowning the other swimmers at a beach to being mandated to save—or indeed, drown—them’ (142). Footnote 23 In this comparison, the duty to act is far more liberty-restricting than the duty to abstain. But compare, instead, being mandated to share one’s sun screen whilst on the beach and being prohibited from setting foot on the beach altogether. Here, the act liability (you are banned from going on the beach) is far greater an imposition than the omissions liability (you are banned from not sharing your sun screen, when on the beach). So there is an ‘all other things being equal’ element to the range-of-alternatives distinction, too. The idea is not that omissions liability is more liberty-reducing across the board, but that any instance of omissions liability sports a feature that positive act liability does not: that for whatever time the corresponding duty to act applies, all other options are foreclosed. If I must rescue a wounded hiker I happen upon on a mountain pass, I am not free to do anything else in the meantime.

Looping back to the previous discussion, there is one order of omissions liability it seems inapt to view as liberty-restricting in this special way. These are the sorts of cases where the omission is in fact just a mode of negligently engaging in some activity. The opportunity costs element is not germane here, it could be argued, once the duty to act is more accurately understood as a duty to perform an activity responsibly, given your choice to perform it. You cannot assume the social role of parenthood without feeding your children. You cannot be an air traffic controller without telling pilots when they are too close to other aircrafts. Liability pegged to failures like these does not exactly amount to coercing people into conduct, to the exclusion of all other options. It is, rather, the legal conditioning of all manner of options: one cannot choose to do that thing in this way. That is indeed a restriction on liberty—being an inattentive air traffic controller is an excluded choice. But it is not a liberty restriction of a wholly different character to the coercive removal of my choice to punch someone, or to smash up some property.

The more straightforward example of the ‘pure omission’—the bystander who elects not to save the drowning child—better lends itself to the analysis according to which a legal duty to act is especially liberty-restricting in blocking all other options. In many cases, Simester rightly says, this liberty consideration is simply outweighed, for instance, where the liberty infringement is minimal, fleeting, and the costs of not acting are severe. Footnote 24 In her widely-read essay about abortion ethics, Judith Thomson imagines that she is on the brink of death, and that the actor Henry Fonda only has to cross a room and place his cool hand on her fevered brow to revive her—the easiest rescue case there is. Footnote 25 Thomson believes Fonda’s refusal would be monstrous, but that his performance is not morally required, a pair of propositions I have always found difficult. What is clear enough, though, is that Fonda’s freedom to pursue other options and to not cross the room—when he is already in the room!—holds hardly any weight against the value of Thomson’s life.

Simester claims that the liberty concern of having all but one option forbidden to us is outweighed in all cases where there is a distinct duty to act. Putting things slightly differently, I might say that the fact it is so grossly outweighed is what explains, in such cases, why there is a duty to act which it would be wrong to shirk. Were things not set up in such a way as to make it horribly unjust for Fonda to refuse, even taking into account his need to live his own life, we would not be looking at such a clear case of a culpable omission.

Can the range-of-alternatives distinction provide the basis for any default rule regarding omissions? It might be thought that the opportunity costs dimension of duties to act favours an especially limited scope of pure omissions liability. For any isolated duty to act, the loss of liberty to the obliged person may well be trivial. (What is it to Henry Fonda if, once in his lifetime, he is obliged to cross a room to save a person?) As Simester remarks, though, a general and recurrent legal duty to act is far more onerous. Footnote 26 It is not easy to specify the exact quota of easy rescues the law can require of one person before it is too demanding, but a general duty to forestall preventable harm whenever it is within one’s power to do so would certainly ask too much. However, a duty to act which is that capacious would not amount to the legal enforcement of our positive moral obligations, for we are not morally obliged to intervene against all the harms we can thwart or lessen. Simester is entirely correct to point out that not all ills can be equally everyone’s business, or we’d never be able to do anything. Moreover, he rightly says, a responsibility system like that—wherein everyone capable of making a difference bears ascriptive responsibility for a bad consequence in equal measure—sit uneasily with our sense of our own agency in the world and of the separateness of persons. Footnote 27 To assimilate everyone who doesn’t pick up some litter with the original litterer, he writes, would ‘weaken the sense of what the original litterer does ’. Footnote 28 I think this right, and also that it is as true of a system of moral responsibility as it is of a system of legal responsibility.

I am in total accord with Simester, then, that some personal connection to or involvement with preventable harm ought to be a condition of omissions liability. But this is, in any case, what is required to identify the breach of a particular duty to act and, hence, any omission that is a candidate for criminalisation. Not all our harmful omissions should trigger the interest of the criminal law, just as not all our harmful acts should. Where, however, the personal duty to act is clear, the refusal iniquitous, and the harmful consequence the law’s business, there is no special reason for regulatory restraint attaching to the fact that it is a culpable omission we are looking at. There is nothing too recurrent or general about obligations meeting this description; any incident meeting the criteria is already atypical, and far from a standing feature of life. So there is no great worry, I think, concerning the burdensomeness of the law’s treating acts and omissions alike, the range-of-alternatives point notwithstanding. It must be remembered, moreover, that the more intrusive and ubiquitous a putative duty to act is , the more footing one has to argue that it does not reflect our actual moral duties.

5 The Bad Samaritan and the Easy Rescue

The lazy bystander who malignly declines an easy rescue has already made several appearances in this discussion. He also tends to be a central figure in the first lesson of my own criminal law undergraduate course, where much of the debate concerns whether the law of England and Wales should recognise the criminal responsibility of the ‘Bad Samaritan’. As Joel Feinberg defines him, the Bad Samaritan is:

(a) a stranger standing in no ‘special relationship’ to the endangered party,

(b) who omits to do something—warn of unperceived peril, undertake rescue, seek aid, notify police, protect against further injury—for the endangered party,

(c) which he could have done without unreasonable cost or risk to himself or others,

(d) as a result of which the other party suffers harm, or an increased degree of harm,

(e) and for these reasons the omitter is ‘bad’ (morally blameworthy). Footnote 29

The refusing Henry Fonda would certainly fit this description of the Bad Samaritan, as would the apocryphal villain who sits reclined, sipping his cocktail, declining to move a muscle, while a toddler in the pool in front of him drowns in two feet of water. It is always perplexing to me just how zealously students work, almost without exception, to rebut the arguments in favour of criminal responsibility for failures of easy rescue of this and less farfetched kinds (as well as how instinctively they identify with the would-be rescuer instead of the imperilled party). Arguments featuring heavily in these discussions include problems of knowledge on the part of the omitter (perhaps it is not obvious that the victim is in such peril, and that he can help, and without unreasonable cost?); the liberty restriction in mandated action; the view that easy rescue liability mandates supererogatory acts; and worries about unbounded categories of duty-breachers and too many Bad Samaritans—i.e. what if you are just one of many people who could have acted but didn’t?

Many of these counter-arguments end up deflating as soon as one builds in the indispensable conditions of a legal duty of easy rescue, for instance, that it is obvious to the omitter what will likely happen if he fails to intervene, obvious that the cost of intervening is reasonable, and that he is singly and especially marked out as able to help. I agree with Simester that we cannot countenance a legal duty to aid that condemns everyone on a packed beach who failed to assist a swimmer in trouble. Footnote 30 In such cases, though, the surplus of potential rescuers undercuts the clear and distinct duty on each would-be rescuer to intervene. The less clear it is to a would-be rescuer that it falls to her to do something (as it would if she were the only one around, or if she were the lifeguard), the weaker the argument that she omitted to help. Too many bystanders can crowd out a clear duty of aid, and with it, ascriptive responsibility for the harm.

None of this tells us why the law ought not to impose a duty to rescue where there is no problem of too many bystanders, and where it is abundantly clear to the duty-bearer that it rests with her to act, as it is if I happen across the wounded hiker on the mountain pass, with no one else around. Furthermore, as Feinberg underscores, the refusal to act in a quintessential easy rescue case is not the refusal to engage in supererogation. Footnote 31 Where the rescue is easy enough, and the costs reasonable, refusing to rescue is not the refusal to go beyond the call of duty, but a refusal to do exactly what duty, what morality, requires. When specified properly, then, a legal duty of easy rescue is not the enforcement of gratuitous benevolence, not the legal requirement to be a Good Samaritan (a figure synonymous with supererogation) at all, but only to do the absolute minimum that morality demands. Footnote 32

There are ample ways of being personally connected to some bad state of affairs one fails to prevent. Being responsible for bringing about that bad state of affairs, or volunteering to ensure against it, are some ways. Being in a unique position of easy rescue is another. Simester is explicit about the fact that nothing in his analysis rules out a legal duty of this kind. Footnote 33 It is only, he says, that the lack of ‘prima facie connection’ to the harm in easy rescue cases—and the general right, we might say, to go about one’s own business without becoming implicated in any preventable harm—underwrites the initial right to not intervene, which must then be overridden by other considerations, such as the negligible costs of acting and what is at stake in not acting. Footnote 34 Again, I would venture a slightly different analysis: a personal connection to the harm can be established by the fact that one is singled out, by fate, as the only person capable of assisting, when it is evidently easy to do so, when the costs of not helping are grave, and so on. Easy rescue cases, defined thusly, pass the personal connection test quite plainly.

It is a sound basic rule that we are not legally on the hook for preventable harms that have nothing specifically to do with us. A duty of easy rescue is not an exception to this rule, though; it is an instantiation of it.

R v Gibbins and Proctor (1918) 13 Cr App Rep 134.

R v Instan [1893] 1 QB 450; R v Stone & Dobinson  [1977] 1 QB 354.

R v Pittwood (1902) 19 TLR 37.

R v Miller [1983] 2 AC 161.

A. Simester, Fundamentals of Criminal Law (henceforth FOCM ) (OUP, 2021), chapter 6, at 133.

FCOM chapter 6, passim .

D. Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events (OUP, 2001) 43.

See R v Hughes [2013] UKSC 56.

R v Kennedy (No 2) [2007] UKHL 38.

R v Evans [2009] 2 Cr App R 10.

See FCOM 148 for Simester’s own reference to this comparison.

R v Adomako [1994] 3 WLR 288.

‘Badly’ here is intended to mean ethically inadequate, not to denote only practical incompetence in the field of activity.

To recapitulate, I acknowledge that this is to subvert Simester’s own question, which is whether the law ought to adopt the default rule that we are not accountable for our ‘not-doings’, understood as any failure to prevent harm, with or without a duty to act. As I have explained above, though, I am not convinced there is a default rule of this kind that applies to not-doings but not to deeds. We are not, and cannot conceivably be, answerable in general for the bad consequences that depend on our actions and inactions. Principles of ascriptive responsibility are called upon, in both cases, to connect bad states of affairs to our agency, via the identification of a specific act or omission. Since that is so, the only default rules I consider ripe for discussion are rules pertaining to the scope of criminal omissions.

FCOM 136-137; 141-143; 150-152.

J. Thomson, ‘A Defense of Abortion’, Philosophy & Public Affairs , 1 (1):47-66 (1971).

J. Feinberg, ‘The Moral and Legal Responsibility of the Bad Samaritan’ in Freedom & Fulfillment (Princeton University Press, 1992) at 175.

Feinberg (above) at 189.

Thomson had this latter standard in mind when she wrote of ‘Minimally Decent Samaritans’.

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Massimo Renzo and all the attendants of the symposium workshop on Andrew Simester’s Fundamentals of Criminal Law for their comments.

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

University of Oxford, Associate Professor of Law, Oxford, United Kingdom

Kate Greasley

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kate Greasley .

Additional information

Publisher’s note.

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ .

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Greasley, K. How Omissions Aren’t Special. Criminal Law, Philosophy (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-023-09711-6

Download citation

Accepted : 03 December 2023

Published : 16 December 2023

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-023-09711-6

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Find a journal
  • Publish with us
  • Track your research

U.S. flag

An official website of the United States government, Department of Justice.

Here's how you know

Official websites use .gov A .gov website belongs to an official government organization in the United States.

Secure .gov websites use HTTPS A lock ( Lock A locked padlock ) or https:// means you’ve safely connected to the .gov website. Share sensitive information only on official, secure websites.

NCJRS Virtual Library

Essays in criminal law, additional details.

Drottninggatan 108 , Box 45150 , Stockholm S-10430 Sweden , Sweden

No download available

Availability, related topics.

Punishable Omissions in the Criminal Law Essay

Omission is a criminal act.

When it comes to the definition of a criminal act, many people are likely to associate it with specific decisions that cause instant harm to property or individuals or have negative long-term consequences. However, in some cases, the failure to take action is also a criminal offense. Punishable omissions are inextricably connected with the presence of legal duties, and they vary based on the character of necessary actions that are omitted.

From moral considerations, fellow citizens are expected to help each other in difficult situations that involve threats to people’s life and health. The gap between being obliged and recommended to take some actions becomes obvious when it comes to criminal omissions. The failure to do something to prevent dangerous crimes or save a person who needs help does not always qualify as an omission since there is a significant difference between moral and legal obligations.

An omission can be regarded as a criminal offense if a person does not react to some situation in a manner required by the law. There are two types of criminal omissions that are dissimilar in terms of their consequences (Samaha, 2017). The first type, the failure to act, involves the lack of actions that can raise awareness about certain crimes and reduce their negative effects (Samaha, 2017). As for the failure to intervene, this term is used to define the inability to take direct actions helping to prevent bodily harm or damage to property (Samaha, 2017). Both types present an interesting research topic since the degree to which they apply to individuals depends on people’s professional duties and other factors.

The failure to act is an offense that can take a variety of forms. The inability to report some criminal acts is among the most common causes related to it (Samaha, 2017). Not all citizens are required to make interventions and take direct actions to stop criminals. However, it is commonly accepted that a person should at least report a crime if he or she knows something or becomes an eyewitness of some illegal acts (Samaha, 2017). As an example, a social worker who knows about a case of child abuse or rape and fails to report it can be subject to punishment since he or she is obliged to protect children’s interests. As for some real-life cases, in 2017, four members of school staff in Marion County were punished for not reporting one student’s complaint about armed threats because of the child’s mental status (Lopardi, 2017). Thus, the inability to provide information about actual or suspected crimes is an important question when it comes to specialists working with people who have no legal capacity.

Speaking about the failure to intervene, this type of criminal omission is often interconnected with specific duties in some professional fields. It occurs when people fail to take actions related to their field of responsibility, thus neglecting their legal duties (Samaha, 2017). Also, the unwillingness to provide necessary help is considered as a criminal omission when there are special links between an affected person and an individual refusing to take action. The links refer to the presence of close familial relationships between children and parents or spouses (Samaha, 2017). Such offenses may also include doctors, police officers, rescue teams’, or transportation companies’ failure to perform actions to provide the safety of their clients.

To sum it up, due to their potential consequences, omissions present an important topic in the field of criminal law. An omission is regarded as a criminal offense if a person fails to fulfill his or her legal responsibilities that exist because of professional duties or the obligation to ensure the safety of one’s spouse or children. Criminal omissions can be presented by the lack of actions to report some important data or take necessary actions in emergency cases.

Lopardi, M. (2017). Marion County elementary school staffers punished for not reporting alleged abuse, district says. WFTV9 . Web.

Samaha, J. (2017). Criminal law (12th ed.). Boston. MA: Cengage Learning.

  • Chicago (A-D)
  • Chicago (N-B)

IvyPanda. (2024, February 23). Punishable Omissions in the Criminal Law. https://ivypanda.com/essays/punishable-omissions-in-the-criminal-law/

"Punishable Omissions in the Criminal Law." IvyPanda , 23 Feb. 2024, ivypanda.com/essays/punishable-omissions-in-the-criminal-law/.

IvyPanda . (2024) 'Punishable Omissions in the Criminal Law'. 23 February.

IvyPanda . 2024. "Punishable Omissions in the Criminal Law." February 23, 2024. https://ivypanda.com/essays/punishable-omissions-in-the-criminal-law/.

1. IvyPanda . "Punishable Omissions in the Criminal Law." February 23, 2024. https://ivypanda.com/essays/punishable-omissions-in-the-criminal-law/.

Bibliography

IvyPanda . "Punishable Omissions in the Criminal Law." February 23, 2024. https://ivypanda.com/essays/punishable-omissions-in-the-criminal-law/.

  • Copyright Implications: Crime Punishable by Law
  • How to Handle Media Manipulation?
  • Supreme Court Decision in the US vs. Bass Case of 2001
  • Analysis of The Code of Hammurabi
  • The Phases of a Crime and Their Importance in Psychological Profiling
  • Healthcare Negligence and Its Criminalization
  • Law: Legislation Regarding Marijuana Farming
  • Affirmative Defense: Dixon v. the United States
  • Disclosing Officer Untruthfulness to the Defense
  • Retributivism and Fallible Systems of Punishment
  • The Case of Terryl Smith, the Oakland Police Officer
  • Philippine Cybercrime Prevention Act Opposition
  • People vs. Goetz: Court Decision and Implications
  • The Concept of School-To-Prison Pipeline Process
  • Cyber Crime in the U.S. and Nigeria

Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.

To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to  upgrade your browser .

Enter the email address you signed up with and we'll email you a reset link.

  • We're Hiring!
  • Help Center

paper cover thumbnail

Omissions in Criminal Law

Profile image of Grainne Denihan

Related Papers

Kris Gledhill

omissions criminal law essay

Liz Campbell

Common law countries share a growing receptiveness to the use of DNA (deoxyribonucleic acid) in criminal investigation and prosecution, with the formalisation and steady expansion of schemes of DNA collection and retention. Despite a general consensus regarding the significance and value of genetic material in criminal justice, there is considerable divergence in terms of the populations from whom DNA may be collected and the length of time for which DNA may be retained. This article takes a comparative approach by assessing the trajectory of the law relating to DNA collection and retention in a range of common law jurisdictions, and ascertains how aspects of particular countries‟ laws seek to resolve common problematic issues that arise concerning human rights, in particular the rights to bodily integrity, of privacy and the presumption of innocence. It identifies a common international movement to a risk-based approach and concludes that of the comparator jurisdictions the Canadian model provides the most fitting accommodation for human rights in DNA database expansion.

Georgia Law Review

rohit ruhani

New Criminal Law Review

John J Child

When looking to identify the basic ingredients of criminal responsibility, reference is standardly made to a voluntary act requirement (VAR). We blame a defendant (D) for what she has done or (perhaps) failed to do where such doing or failing to do is proscribed by law; we do not punish mere thoughts or character. However, despite the continued appeal of the VAR in abstract principle, the precise definitions and restrictions entailed within it are not always clear, and its usefulness in preventing inappropriate criminalisation is openly (and in many cases correctly) challenged. Principally, and crucially, the VAR has received sustained attack in recent years from critics within the philosophies of action, highlighting its descriptive and normative shortcomings. It is contended that such criticism is misplaced. This article provides defence to a stripped-back definition of the VAR, distinguishing the general definition of action in philosophy from the definition of action within the criminal law, and seeking to identify and preserve a doctrinally workable model of the latter.

Elizabeth Yuko

Darius Whelan

Pregnant Woman and Unborn Child: Legal Adversaries

Gerard Casey

Edward Mathews

A study of the criminalisation of HIV exposure and transmission and exposure, considering the philosophical underpinnings of criminalisation, elements of the offences prosecuted in England and Canada, specific offences in the USA, the public health implications of criminalisation and the potential for criminalisation in Ireland.

RELATED PAPERS

Dublin University Law Journal

David Prendergast

Yanitsa Stoeva

Theoretical Inquiries in Law

jeremy horder

Alex Sharpe

Eimear Spain

JESÚS MARIA SILVA SANCHEZ

marilyn mcmahon

Thomas Crofts

onder bakircioglu

Mihai Risnoveanu

Northern Ireland Legal Quarterly

Mohnish Mathew

Shabbir Shiddiky

Jennie Guerzon

Ian Leader-Elliott

Jacobo Dopico

Paul Johnstone

[email protected] Keenan

Kings Law Journal (2018) 29(3)

Alisdair Gillespie

Bernard NTAHIRAJA

Jonathan Jackson

Denni Honcho

Revolutionary Genders , Sibéal Feminist and Gender Studies Network

RELATED TOPICS

  •   We're Hiring!
  •   Help Center
  • Find new research papers in:
  • Health Sciences
  • Earth Sciences
  • Cognitive Science
  • Mathematics
  • Computer Science
  • Academia ©2024

Subscribe to the newsletter

The developer began an inspection after a mass fight between workers in the east of moscow.

On April 14, a mass fight between workers occurred in the east of Moscow; the developer Brusnika, at whose site the fight occurred, is conducting an internal inspection.

“No one was injured during the incident. Together with the contractor, we began an internal review. The conflict will be resolved soon. It will not affect the construction timeline,” the company’s press service told RBC.

A RIA Novosti source in law enforcement agencies clarified that the cause of the collision was a conflict over the distribution of reinforcement between brigades. The agency reports that among the participants in the fight at the construction site of the Metronom Quarter project there were 16 citizens of Tajikistan and 14 citizens of Uzbekistan.

On April 14, the capital’s Investigative Committee reported that department officials were identifying those involved in the mass brawl. In connection with this, the Investigative Committee for Moscow opened a criminal case under Art. 213 of the Criminal Code (“Hooliganism”).

“Persons involved in the crime will be checked for compliance with migration laws,” the department added.

On April 14, a fight broke out in the center of Saratov at the intersection of Chapaev Street and Stolypin Avenue, near the Volga Hotel. The driver of a Lada Priora intervened and hit one person. In the video, which was published on social networks, some participants in the conflict jumped on the car, one of the passengers jumped out of it while it was moving, then the car drove into a building.

IMAGES

  1. Ommissions essay plan

    omissions criminal law essay

  2. Criminal Law Cases

    omissions criminal law essay

  3. Criminal law

    omissions criminal law essay

  4. Omissions

    omissions criminal law essay

  5. (PDF) Norris,A. Criminal Omissions Essay

    omissions criminal law essay

  6. Criminal Law Lecture Two

    omissions criminal law essay

VIDEO

  1. Criminal Law: Omissions

  2. Evaluation of omissions

  3. Crime and Punishment by Fyodor Dostoyevsky

  4. Criminal History Inquiries & Fair Chance Hiring

  5. Insanity Defense: Andrea Yates’ Criminal Case

  6. Omissions

COMMENTS

  1. Treatment of Omission in Criminal Law

    'The criminal law is right to treat acts differently to omissions.' Discuss. Introduction. The author in this essay will critically discuss whether it is the correct approach for acts to have a distinct treatment than omissions.Would treating omissions in the same manner as acts be inconsistent with other interests which criminal law should protect, such as principle of authority, legality ...

  2. A Critical Analysis of the Criminalisation of Omissions

    This essay aims to critically analyse the place of omissions within the criminal law, which traditionally has primarily focused on acts of commission which result in harm to another. However, in certain circumstances, it can penalise an act of omission, which is 'something which is not done in circumstances where there is some reason or expectation for that thing to be done'.

  3. Criminal law essay on omissions

    This essay will outline the principles on omissions and demonstrate the current law to be largely unsatisfactory due to its implications on essential common law principles of natural justice. The current law governing criminal liability for omissions is satisfactory in its capability to acknowledge and deter harmful consequences that can result ...

  4. Omissions and Criminal Liability

    DUTIES TO ACT. As already noted, the distinctive feature of omissions liability is nition (or creation) by the law of a pre-existing or extraneous duty circumstances which can attract criminal liability. The identification. duties has, in the main, been judicially undertaken and, in line.

  5. Omissions in Criminal Law

    Omissions in Criminal Law. criminal-law. 10 Jul. Written By Law Tutor. In English law there is no liability for failing to act. A person is under no obligation to assist another in peril unless they belong to a specific category which creates a duty to act. For example a passer-by has no legal duty to aid a drowning person, whereas a parent has ...

  6. Omissions (Chapter 2)

    Robinson, P. H., ' Criminal Liability for Omissions: A Brief Summary and Critique of the Law in the United States ', New York Law School Law Review 29 (1984), 101-27. Google Scholar Romano , M. , Commentario sistematico del Codice penale , 3 vols. Milan , Giuffré ( 2004 ), I. Google Scholar

  7. Criminal law essay on omission

    ESSAY2- A Critical Analysis of the Criminalization of Omissions. Samuel Carthy. Introduction. This essay aims to critically analyse the place of omissions within the criminal law, which traditionally has primarily focused on acts of commission which result in harm to another.

  8. PDF A New Generation of Omissions Offences

    generation of omissions offences, taking criminal responsibility to a new level, and this will ... Criminal Law: Essays in Honour of J.C. Smith (Butterworths, 1987); A. Ashworth and L. Zedner, Preventive Justice (2014), 96-98; and J. Horder, 'Harmless Wrongdoing and the Anticipatory Perspective on Criminalisation', in G.R. Sullivan and I.

  9. Beyond acts and omissions: remark-able criminal conduct

    3. Simester, AP 'Causation in (criminal) law' (2017) 133 LQR 416 Google Scholar at 440-441. 4. As I use it, the term 'conduct-token' is neutral as to whether the agent's conduct was an act or an omission. 5. Ashworth, A Positive Obligations in Criminal Law (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2013) p 31 Google Scholar; Simester, AP 'Why ...

  10. How Omissions Aren't Special

    The criminal acts and omissions recognised by law are alternative routes to ascribing responsibility to agents for certain consequences and distinguishing those consequences from mere happenings and events. Both doctrines, we might say, fulfil the function of delimiting the states of affairs for which we are answerable, against the more basic ...

  11. PDF Dunbar, James Robertson (2012) Criminal liability for omissions in

    It is the 'omission' itself which is criminal and the accused is penalised for the 'failure' to do something. In modern Scots law the vast majority of such offences would be contained in statute10. The second type of case is that of 'commission by omission'.

  12. Essays in Criminal Law

    The third essay explores criminal liability for omissions in terms of the guarantor doctrine, carelessness, and vicarious liability. The fourth essay addresses determinism and criminal responsibility with emphasis on punishment, excuses, rationality, personhood, freedom, responsibility, blame and punishment, and desert and punishment.

  13. Acts & Omissions Criminal Law

    This essay affirms that it is possible to draw a distinction; albeit not a clear one. A distinction is important in order to avoid overlooking omissions, which can form a basis for criminal liability; and in the doctrine of actus novus interveniens. A clear distinction is seen in the definitions of an act and omission.

  14. Two Models of 'Absence of Movement' in Criminal Jurisprudence

    This essay critiques that approach and points to the fact that American jurisprudence is not uniform with regard to the definition of act and omission in the criminal-law context. The essay suggests that this lack of uniformity springs from the differing rationales that underpin the distinction between act and omission in criminal jurisprudence.

  15. Punishable Omissions in the Criminal Law Essay

    An omission can be regarded as a criminal offense if a person does not react to some situation in a manner required by the law. There are two types of criminal omissions that are dissimilar in terms of their consequences (Samaha, 2017). The first type, the failure to act, involves the lack of actions that can raise awareness about certain ...

  16. (DOC) Omissions in Criminal Law

    Relying on academic literature and cases I will seek to further my understanding of this particular aspect of criminal law. An omission differs from an act. An act is seen as an active, positive act, while an omission is negative in nature. McAuley and McCutcheon, 'Criminal Liability', (2000) (MPG Books) at p. 180.

  17. Criminal Law on Omission

    The Law Commission in its Draft Criminal Code of 1989 states that death caused by such an offence can be caused by an omission 2. In common law, certain obligations have lead to statutory enactments. An example is R v Gibbins and Proctor 3, in which a man and his cohabiting partner deliberately withheld food from the child for whom they had ...

  18. Crminal Law, Omissions essay

    Ashworth A, and Horder J, Principles Of Criminal Law (7th edn, Oxford University Press 2013) Herring J, Criminal Law (9th edn, ... Crminal Law, Omissions essay. Module: Criminal Law (LAW 1260) 231 Documents. Students shared 231 documents in this course. University: University of Leeds. Info More info. Download.

  19. C.l.j. 539

    invaluable case commentaries in the Criminal Law Review, or in his longer articles and books on the criminal law. The quality of the essays in this festschrift form a fitting tribute to his academic excellence. From the introductory essay we also learn some other snippets about John Smith, such C.L.J. 539

  20. Award stigma of war criminals from the Russian Army, database and video

    Order of Courage. State award of the Russian Federation. The Order of Courage is awarded to citizens for their dedication, courage, and bravery shown during the rescue operations, in protecting of public order, in the fight against crime, in response operations to natural disasters, fires, accidents and other emergencies, as well as for brave and decisive actions in the line of military or ...

  21. The developer began an inspection after a mass fight between workers in

    The Investigative Committee opened a criminal case in connection with this under Art. 213 of the Criminal Code ("Hooliganism") PROPAGANDA - Warning this article may contain misinformation intended to manipulate your opinion - Russie - All items "RBC" This image may be subject to copyright (see info at the end of the article). ...

  22. Elektrostal

    Elektrostal, city, Moscow oblast (province), western Russia.It lies 36 miles (58 km) east of Moscow city. The name, meaning "electric steel," derives from the high-quality-steel industry established there soon after the October Revolution in 1917. During World War II, parts of the heavy-machine-building industry were relocated there from Ukraine, and Elektrostal is now a centre for the ...

  23. Moscow

    Moscow, city, capital of Russia, located in the far western part of the country.Since it was first mentioned in the chronicles of 1147, Moscow has played a vital role in Russian history. It became the capital of Muscovy (the Grand Principality of Moscow) in the late 13th century; hence, the people of Moscow are known as Muscovites.Today Moscow is not only the political centre of Russia but ...