Red Comet

AP English Language and Composition

Course features:.

  • Recommended Grade Level: 9-12
  • Course Credits: 1
  • Course Price: $299.00

Course Overview:

An Advanced Placement course in English Language and Composition engages students in becoming skilled readers of prose written in a variety of periods, disciplines, and rhetorical contexts and in becoming skilled writers who compose for a variety of purposes. Both their writing and their reading should make students aware of the interactions among a writer’s purposes, audience expectations, and subjects as well as the way generic conventions and the resources of language contribute to effectiveness in writing. The college composition course for which the AP English Language and Composition course substitutes is one of the most varied in the curriculum.

Required Materials:

You will need the following items to complete this course:

  • Disk space on your computer, as well as an external device to back up your files (flash drive, external hard drive, CD-Rom, etc.)
  • Word processing and presentation software
  • It is recommended that students purchase a test preparation book to work on independently. Speak to your instructor about which test prep book might be most appropriate.
  • Students will need to obtain the following texts, either from a library or a bookseller:

Segment One:

  • Civil War Edition: Choose one of the following:
  • Zen in the Art of Writing by Ray Bradbury
  • On Writing Well by William Zinsser

Segment Two:

Contemporary Edition: See the lesson entitled The Memoir for an overview of text choices and choose one of the following:

  • **Narrative of the Life of Frederick Douglass by Frederick Douglass
  • *A Work in Progress: A Memoir by Connor Franta
  • The Reason I Jump: The Inner Voice of a Thirteen-Year-Old Boy with Autism by Naoki Higashida
  • *The Color of Water: A Black Man's Tribute to His White Mother by James McBride
  • *The Glass Castle: A Memoir by Jeannette Walls
  • *I am Malala: The Girl Who Stood Up for Education and Was Shot by the Taliban by Malala Yousafza
  • *I Know Why the Caged Bird Sings by Maya Angelou
  • Dust Tracks on a Road by Zora Neale Hurston
  • ***Incidents in the Life of a Slave Girl by Harriet Jacobs
  • **The Story of My Life by Helen Keller

Student Edition: See the Checklist lesson for an overview of text choices and choose one of the following:

  • Pilgrim at Tinker Creek by Annie Dillard
  • *Nickel and Dimed: On (Not) Getting By in America by Barbara Ehrenreich
  • Mountains Beyond Mountains: The Quest of Dr. Paul Farmer, A Man Who Would Cure the World by Tracy Kidder
  • *The Devil in the White City: Murder, Magic, and Madness at the Fair that Changed America by Erik Larson
  • **Up from Slavery: An Autobiography by Booker T. Washington
  • Into Thin Air by Jon Krakauer
  • The Immortal Life of Henrietta Lacks by Rebecca Skloot
  • Warmth of Other Suns by Isabell Wilkerson
  • Bury My Heart At Wounded Knee by Dee Brown
  • The Boys in the Boat by Daniel James Brown

* All works have rhetorical merit for the AP English student; texts marked with asterisks deal with mature subject matter or contain adult language or situations. If this is a concern for you or your family, please choose a different text from the list.

** This text can be read online.

Early Edition

  • 01.00 Early Edition: Checklist
  • 01.01 AP English Language and Composition Overview
  • 01.02 Analyzing Texts
  • 01.03 Claims and Evidence
  • 01.04 Introduction to Rhetorical Strategies
  • 01.05 Critical Reading and Rhetorical Analysis
  • 01.06 The Free Response
  • 01.07 Evaluating Student Responses
  • 01.08 Early Edition: Discussion-Based Assessment

Revolutionary Edition

  • 02.00 Revolutionary Edition: Checklist
  • 02.01 Historical Context: Writers React
  • 02.02 Introduction to Argument
  • 02.03 Structure as Rhetorical Strategy
  • 02.04 Supporting the Argument
  • 02.05 Evaluating Arguments
  • 02.06 Aphorisms
  • 02.07 Tone and Argument
  • 02.08 AP Practice Essay One
  • 02.09 Crafting Compound and Complex Sentences
  • 02.10 Revolutionary Edition: Discussion-Based Assessment
  • 02.11 AP Practice Essay Two

Romantic Edition

  • 03.00 Romantic Edition: Checklist
  • 03.01 Multiple Choice: Reader and Writer
  • 03.02 Figurative Language in Argument
  • 03.03 The Power of Diction
  • 03.04 Taking a Position
  • 03.05 Establishing a Line of Reasoning
  • 03.06 Analyzing Syntax
  • 03.07 AP Practice Essay Three
  • 03.08 Crafting Periodic and Loose Sentences
  • 03.09 Developing Commentary
  • 03.10 Romantic Edition: Discussion-Based Assessment

Civil War Edition

  • 04.00 Civil War Edition: Checklist
  • 04.01 Multiple Choice: Read Stems First
  • 04.02 Reading About Writing
  • 04.03 Elements of Style
  • 04.04 AP Practice Essay Four
  • 04.05 Speech Analysis
  • 04.06 Multiple Choice: Predict the Answer
  • 04.07 Analyzing Style
  • 04.08 Civil War Edition: Discussion-Based Assessment
  • 04.09 Crafting Periodic and Balanced Sentences
  • 04.10 AP Practice Essay Five
  • 04.11 Reading and Synthesis
  • 04.12 Nonfiction Book Journal
  • 04.13 Segment One Exam

Realism Edition

  • 05.00 Realism Edition: Checklist
  • 05.01 Understanding Satire
  • 05.02 Political Cartoons
  • 05.03 "A Modest Proposal"
  • 05.04 That's So Ironic
  • 05.05 Irony to Ignite
  • 05.06 Analyzing Satire
  • 05.07 Exploring the Satirical Prompt
  • 05.08 Multiple Choice: Find the Focus
  • 05.09 AP Practice Essay Six
  • 05.10 Crafting Chiasmus and Anaphora
  • 05.11 AP Practice Essay Seven
  • 05.12 Realism Edition: Discussion-Based Assessment

Modern Edition

  • 06.00 Modern Edition: Checklist
  • 06.01 Multiple Choice: Eliminate Answer Choices
  • 06.02 Meet the Synthesis Essay
  • 06.03 Conversations and Claims
  • 06.04 Synthesizing the Voices of the Harlem Renaissance
  • 06.05 Cultivating Commentary Using Sources
  • 06.06 An Image is Worth 1,000 Words
  • 06.07 Evaluating Student Responses
  • 06.08 Planning a Response
  • 06.09 Modern Edition: Discussion-Based Assessment
  • 06.10 Crafting Purposeful Structure
  • 06.11 AP Practice Essay Eight

Contemporary Edition

  • 07.00 Contemporary Edition: Checklist
  • 07.01 Multiple Choice: Putting It All Together
  • 07.02 The Memoir
  • 07.03 Appeals in Argument
  • 07.04 AP Practice Essay Nine
  • 07.05 Rhetoric in Action
  • 07.06 AP Practice Essay Ten
  • 07.07 Evaluate and Implement
  • 07.08 AP Practice Essay Eleven
  • 07.09 Crafting Sentence Variety
  • 07.10 Memoir Journal
  • 07.11 Contemporary Edition: Discussion-Based Assessment

Student Edition

  • 08.00 Student Edition: Checklist
  • 08.01 Research the Context
  • 08.02 Analyze the Author's Choices
  • 08.03 Argue an Issue
  • 08.04 Pick a Perspective
  • 08.05 Create a Connection
  • 08.06 Interpret Rhetorical Strategies
  • 08.07 Student Edition: Discussion-Based Assessment
  • 08.08 Segment Two Exam

Awards, Approvals, and Accreditation

06.09 practice essay nine

© 2024 - RedComet.org. All rights reserved.

websights

1997.6.9, Striker, Essays on Hellenistic Epistemology and Ethics

William stephens , creighton university. [email protected].

This volume is a collection of fifteen essays (seven on epistemology, eight on ethics), all but one of which are articles previously published between 1974 and 1994. The one new essay, “Methods of sophistry”, is the opening chapter. Chapter Two, “ κριτήριον τῆς ἀληθείας ,” and Chapter Six, “On the difference between the Pyrrhonists and the Academics”, were originally published in German, and are translated into English in this volume.

In the preface the author declares that “these essays are first and foremost a contribution to the history of philosophy” (ix), but that they are written from the perspective of a philosopher interested in the merits and weaknesses of the philosophical theories and the arguments designed to support them (x). She proceeds to offer compelling reasons for challenging the common, pat division of philosophical studies into “systematic” and “historical”, making a convincing case that historical exegesis contributes to contemporary philosophical debate by “keeping available the thought of past philosophers as a resource that would otherwise be lost or inaccessible” (xii). Scholars of Hellenistic philosophy will certainly welcome the convenience of having all these important works of a leading scholar in the field under one cover. I will offer sketches of each chapter with some few critical remarks, and I will end with some general comments.

In “Methods of sophistry” Striker reasons that since philosophy and rhetoric were not established as distinct disciplines until the fourth century B.C., the Sophists of the fifth century B.C. ought to be considered neither philosophers nor rhetoricians (3). She argues that “the philosophical part of what the Sophists did, and taught their pupils to do, would be most accurately described by the term “dialectic” in Aristotle’s—not Plato’s—sense, and that recognizing this may help us better to understand the aims and perhaps even the content of the Sophists’ (mostly lost) writings” (3-4). Striker finds reason to agree with Plato that antilogic was the core of the Sophists’ craft (8). She gives two reasons for concurring with Aristotle’s judgment that the Sophists were dialecticians and not philosophers. First, the dialectician will argue from ἔνδοξα (commonly accepted premises that may or may not be true), whereas the philosopher will try to argue only from true premises. Second, the dialectician will be able to provide arguments for each of two contradictory theses, whereas the philosopher will try to decide which one of the contradictories is true and which is false. In the second half of this essay Striker presents “a brief and superficial look” at Gorgias’ “On What is Not” and Protagoras’ “Truth.” She contends that in the former Gorgias was not advocating the philosophical claim that nothing can be known, but was simply trying to show that Parmenides’ reasoning leads nowhere (14). Her reconstruction of the latter leads her to claim that “we do not need to see in Protagoras’ treatise an early essay in systematic epistemology. Rather, he might once again have been engaged in producing an ἀντιλογία ” (18).

Now the reader may well wonder why this essay on figures in the fifth century B.C. belongs in a collection of essays on Hellenistic philosophy. The explanation is to be found in the final section of the essay, where Striker judges that “the importance of the Sophists’ activity should be appreciated … not in terms of their alleged theories, but in terms of the enormous and inspiring influence their arguments had on the theories developed after their time” (18). She claims that “it would be a mistake to treat Protagoras as, say, the founder of Skepticism, thereby reading later views back into his arguments” (19), and concludes by trying to illustrate this for the case of the Pyrrhonist Skeptics. Thus this first chapter succeeds, I think, in providing an appropriate kind of historical introduction to the essays that follow it.

The second chapter is one of the longest. Striker argues that the philosophical phrase κριτήριον τῆς ἀληθείας was understood to mean “a means for evaluating everything which can be characterized as true or false” (24). She suggests the possibility that it was Epicurus who first made the term κριτήριον a common expression in philosophical language (29). She contends that Epicurus’ theory of criteria is not really a theory of knowledge, but rather “a theory of science—a theory of how, from certain given pieces of knowledge, we can arrive at further knowledge” (51). Striker proceeds to show how this fundamentally distinguishes Epicurus’ theory from the Stoic doctrine of the criterion based on the καταληπτικὴ φαντασία , which belongs to the theory of perceptual knowledge.

In Chapter Three, “Epicurus on the truth of sense impressions”, Striker sets out to do three things. First, she suggests that the usual English formulation of Epicurus’ dictum “All sensations are true” is misleading, and should instead be understood as “All sense impressions are true”. Second, she questions the basis of the standard interpretation of this thesis, which is that the word ἀληθές in this context must mean “real” rather than “true”. Third, she proposes a fresh interpretation, taking ἀληθές in the traditional sense of “true”, and she addresses some objections raised against earlier versions of the traditional view (77).

Striker opens Chapter Four, “Sceptical strategies”, by characterizing ‘Scepticism’ as “a thesis, viz. that nothing can be known, and a recommendation, viz. that one should suspend judgement on all matters” (92). Here Striker is uncharacteristically careless in attributing a decidedly dogmatic thesis and a dangerously dogmatic recommendation to the Pyrrhonian sceptics, who strictly report that it appears to them that nothing can be known (in the dogmatist’s sense), and so it appears that they should suspend judgment on all dogmatic claims. Thus she is simply wrong to claim that “the more radical Pyrrhonist position … does indeed exclude the possibility of justified belief” (95); Sextus Empiricus is too scrupulous a Pyrrhonist to dogmatically deny the possibility of justified belief. Striker cites PH I 33-4 as evidence that the argument for the isosthenia of contradictory propositions in the fields of sense perception and theory “eventually acquired the paradoxical status of a dogma of Pyrrhonian scepticism” (95n), yet I see nothing in the passage cited that supports such an interpretation. On the other hand, later in the chapter Striker appears to correct herself by remarking that if Carneades presented his epistemological theory “as his own view, he must be considered, at least in Sextus’ sense, as a dogmatist” (108) and that the Pyrrhonist “acts in accordance with what appears to him to be the case without committing himself to the truth of his impressions” (112n).

Striker’s primary concern in Chapter Five, “The Ten Tropes of Aenesidemus”, is the structure of the Tropes as they are presented in Philo Alexandrinus ( De ebr. 169-202), Sextus Empiricus ( PH I 36-163), and Diogenes Laertius (IX 79-88). She tries to show that “there are indeed two forms of argument used in the Tropes, neither of which coincides with the classical argument of modern skepticism based upon the representative theory of perception” (119).

In the sixth chapter Striker tries to justify her impression that the differences between the Academics and the Pyrrhonists are not simply due to the admittedly very different styles of the two authors, Cicero and Sextus Empiricus. She argues that the two ancient movements represent two models of skeptical philosophy, and she thinks it worthwhile to sketch their outlines “quite apart from whether the differences between the epistemological positions of the historical characters involved have been captured” (136). In her judgment both the Academics and the Pyrrhonists were “chiefly concerned to show that the speculative projects of philosophers are hopeless—the Academics, by producing for every thesis an equally well-grounded counterthesis (sometimes both at the same time), the Pyrrhonists, by doing this, of course, and also by rejecting explicitly the dogmatist’s enterprise of discovering the reality behind confused and contradictory appearances” (147). One final point Striker mentions is that the Pyrrhonist skeptic who is practiced in the tropes, and who has thereby reached ἐποχή (suspension of judgment), “surprisingly finds himself in the state which the dogmatists had been concerned to attain through their search for truth: after ἐποχή , tranquillity follows like a shadow after a body” (148). Striker finds this to be an astonishing and unconvincing announcement, and she is instead inclined to believe David Hume’s experience of falling into “a deep melancholy and pessimism” at the end of one’s skeptical reflections (148).

Here, I think, Striker does not understand the nature of the Pyrrhonist’s discovery. The dogmatist presumes that ἀταραξία will be found only by embracing doctrines that (he avers) are certain truths. But what the Pyrrhonist skeptic discovers in his search for knowledge, as he repeatedly matches each of the dogmatist’s arguments with equally plausible counter-arguments, is that though knowledge seems unattainable, knowledge is in fact unnecessary for a tranquil life. Rather, the skeptic serendipitously comes to see that he can live a tranquil life guided by appearances and everyday observances (Sextus PH I 23-24) without making any dogmatic claims of certainty. This is what I take to be the point of the story of the painter Apelles who, unable to represent the lather on a horse’s mouth successfully, threw his sponge at the picture thereby producing exactly the representation of the lather he wanted ( PH I 28). Striker is not surprised that “the Pyrrhonists do not seem to have attracted much of a following with their recipe for attaining tranquillity” (148), but this is an odd sort of criticism since it is equally true that neither the Epicureans nor the Stoics attracted much of a following among the general populace with their recipes either. Perhaps Striker’s astonishment can be explained by the fact that the ancient Pyrrhonists, unlike Hume (and us), did not live in a society so pervaded by the Christian assumption that truth must reside in dogmatic belief.

Chapter Seven, “The problem of the criterion”, does not fit well with the other six essays on epistemology. This essay was Striker’s contribution to the volume edited by S. Everson, Epistemology (Cambridge University Press, 1990). Her treatment of the criterion (or criteria) of truth in Epicurus, the Stoics, and the Sceptics here seems more of a shallow survey by comparison with the depth of analysis in other essays in this volume. What is worse, some of the discussion in this chapter overlaps with the more extensive discussions of the first several chapters, and so much of this seventh essay seems superfluous to this volume.

“Greek ethics and moral theory”, the eighth chapter, opens the second half of the volume. Striker observes that ancient Greek ethical theories have been judged superior to modern utilitarian and Kantian ethical theories in three respects. First, the Greek authors were concerned with providing an account of the good life, eudaimonia , as opposed to focusing narrowly on right action. Second, this eudaimonistic approach allowed the Greek philosophers “to treat seriously and without philistine prejudices the question of motives for morality, or reasons for wanting to be good” (169). Third, the Greeks were more concerned with virtues of character, that is, dispositions to act in the right way than with principles of right action. Bernard Williams’ pessimism about the enterprise of moral philosophy, namely that modern ethics is inadequate and that ancient ethics was better but based on assumptions we can no longer accept, is judged to be premature by Striker, and her agenda in this essay is “to take a closer look at the development of Greek ethical theories in the hope of finding out how ancient and modern questions might hang together” (170). She contends that the most fundamental question for modern moral theorists is “the justification of moral decisions or the foundation of moral rules” (170), and that Plato’s and Aristotle’s apparent neglect of this question “need not be seen as a repudiation of the whole problem nor as evidence of some deeper insight” (176). Striker makes the case that the Hellenistic theories of Epicurus and the Stoics addressed the question of justification in promising and illuminating ways. She concludes that “The distinction we ought to preserve is not the contrast between prudence and morality but rather that between planning one’s own life and setting up rules for the life of a community” (182).

In Chapter Nine, “ Ataraxia : Happiness as tranquillity”, Striker argues that “tranquillity [ tranquillitas, euthymia, athambia, galene, hesychia, eustatheia ] was in fact not a serious contender for the position of ultimate good in ancient times. Greek theories of happiness from Plato to Epicurus were attempts to spell out what sort of life one would have to lead in order to have good reasons for feeling tranquil or contented; they were not recipes for reaching a certain state of mind” (183). For Epicurus, she observes, tranquillity is itself a pleasure consisting in being free from all troubles or anxiety, “a state of contentment and inner calm that arises from the thought that one has or can easily get all that one needs, and has no reason to be afraid of anything in the future” (187). For the Stoics, tranquillity arises from the knowledge that one has and cannot lose the only real good, virtue. Striker holds that “the main reason for the Stoic sage’s imperturbability lies in his complete indifference to everything bodily or external, and his consequent freedom from emotion, apatheia ” (187). Yet her remark about Seneca’s explication of Stoic contentment is even more insightful: “He [Seneca] enthusiastically describes the immense joy and infinite serenity of the person who has finally achieved virtue. The sage will rejoice in a wonderful sense of relief and freedom, realizing that he has reached absolute security—nothing in this world can present a danger for him any more” (188).

Again, I think, Striker misconstrues the meaning of the Pyrrhonian anecdote about how the painter Apelles’ thrown sponge resulted in a successful representation of the foam at the horse’s muzzle, an anecdote crucial for understanding how the skeptic arrives at tranquillity (192-3).

The anecdote is meant to bring out that reaching tranquillity is a matter of lucky coincidence, not an expected result—and indeed the Skeptic was said to have started from the hope of gaining tranquillity by finding the truth, not by discovering that he is unable to find it. Yet the story is slightly odd because it will only serve to recommend skepticism as a way to tranquillity if one is inclined to believe that the unexpected experience can be repeated. And this is indeed implied when Sextus says, repeating a phrase that recurs in other sources (cf. DL IX 107), that tranquillity follows suspension of judgment “as the shadow follows the body.” That , of course, is not a lucky coincidence. The skeptic must in a way expect to find tranquillity at the end of his journey, but it is probably important that he should not set out with that expectation right from the start because then, surely, he would begin to worry about his chances of success (imagine Apelles adopting sponge-throwing as a painting technique). Skeptical tranquillity can only be reached if one does not try for it.

I would contend that the skeptic’s tranquillity results from serendipity, which is not simply a matter of lucky coincidence. What the skeptic learns is that it is not dogmatism, but rather epoche (suspension of judgment), that produces ataraxia. While Striker is right that it is not a lucky coincidence that the shadow follows the body, we should remember that this does not happen on cloudy days, so we need not suppose that tranquillity always or necessarily follows suspension of judgment. Moreover, surely it is only the dogmatist, and never the skeptic, who would worry about his chances of success. Skeptical tranquillity can only be reached if one does not try for it directly. Striker writes that the skeptic “had better not believe that tranquillity itself is a good, lest he begin to worry about that” (193), but of course the canny skeptic would merely say that tranquillity appears to him to be a good. No genuine Pyrrhonian skeptic would hold the dogmatic belief that it is a good. But despite her misinterpretation of this “subtle story” (193) in Pyrrhonism, Striker ends this essay on target. She observes that “the thesis that happiness is just a state of mind leads to the conclusion that neither one’s moral character nor the truth or falsity of one’s convictions has anything to do with one’s happiness” (194); the Epicureans and the Stoics proposed no such thesis since “they saw their task as determining what should count as a real good, and eventually to show that a happy life required virtue” (195).

Chapter Ten contains a discussion of the difficulty of how Epicurus’ position that the highest good is a state of absence of pain and trouble from body and soul is a version of hedonism. Striker carefully studies Cicero De fin. I to set the contrast between the Cyrenaics and Epicurus in a different light and thereby reflect on interesting problems about the role of pleasure as the final good. She convincingly argues that for Epicurus “there were exactly two katastematic pleasures, namely aponia and ataraxia , that together make up complete pleasure” (207). She suggests that he “introduced the notion of katastematic pleasure in order to show that happiness can be the same as pleasure after all, provided that one is willing to accept as pleasures not only episodes of enjoyment, but also those states that, according to Epicurus, make one’s life enjoyable at every moment” (207-8). Striker says that “both the thesis that pleasure is nothing but undisturbed affection and perhaps even more the claim that all mental pleasures are parasitic upon bodily ones are highly implausible” (208), and so she judges the Cyrenaics to be better hedonists than Epicurus since they paid more attention to the complicated and varied phenomena described as pleasures.

Chapter Eleven, “Origins of the concept of natural law”, is one of the shortest, but most lucid, essays in this volume. I believe that Striker succeeds in establishing that the Stoics were the original authors of this concept. She persuasively argues that “The Stoic theory … was meant to be a revised version of Socratic moral theory, one that could be defended against Plato’s and Aristotle’s objections” (215). She poses two questions: why was the theory of natural law introduced, and what problems was it meant to solve? She answers:

It offers a solution to the problem of objectivity by appealing to nature as setting standards that are independent of human conventions or beliefs. It also offers a solution to the problem of congruence by claiming that happiness, or a good human life, will be achieved precisely by organizing one’s life in accordance with the rational pattern provided by nature. Both these solutions are very different from the ones given by Plato and Aristotle. The difference can perhaps be described like this: while Plato and Aristotle start from the notion of justice as a good or right state of affairs, or action apt to produce such a state, and then describe good or just laws as necessarily imperfect prescriptions about how to achieve such a good state, the Stoics begin with the notion of goodness as rational order and regularity, and then define virtue and just conduct in terms of obedience to the laws of nature. (219)

My only criticism pertains to Striker’s discussion of justice in Plato’s Republic. She claims that “notoriously Plato does not give us a definition of this Form in the Republic ” (212), and that “Justice is described as that state of soul or city in which its parts are arranged in the right hierarchical order and fulfill their separate functions well” (213). Yet Socrates does, in fact, hint in Book III that justice is ‘minding one’s own business’, τὰ ἑαυτοῦ πράττειν (406e). In Book IV he seems to present this as an explicit definition: τὸ τὰ αὐτοῦ πράττειν καὶ μὴ πολυπραγμονεῖν δικαιοσύνη ἐστί (433a); τοῦτο … κινδυνεύει τρόπον τινὰ γιγνόμενον ἡ δικαιοσύνη εἶναι , τὸ τὰ αὐτοῦ πράττειν (433b). This definition is further explicated as ‘the having and doing of one’s own and what belongs to one’, καὶ ταύτῃ ἄρα πῃ τοῦ οἰκείου τε καὶ ἑαυτοῦ ἕξις τε καὶ πρᾶξις δικαιοσύνη ἂν ὁμολογοῖτο (433e; cf. 434c, 443cd, Book IX 586e, and Book X 620c). It is odd that Striker fails to mention τὸ τὰ αὐτοῦ πράττειν , much less consider its candidacy as Plato’s definition of justice in the Republic.

The lengthy twelfth chapter, “Following nature: A study in Stoic ethics”, is a revised version of Striker’s six Nellie-Wallace lectures delivered at Oxford University in 1984 and later published in Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy IX (1991). Her aim is to offer a more or less historical sketch of the development of Stoic ethics in order to illustrate how their doctrines on nature, reason, morality, and the goal of life hang together. In the first section Striker addresses the question of why it is good to follow nature. In the second section she investigates Chrysippus’ objections to Aristo’s definition of the goal of life as indifference ( adiaphoria ) to what is between virtue and vice, concluding that Chrysippus was probably more concerned than Zeno or Cleanthes about providing a coherent, systematic structure for Stoic doctrine and that his definition of the goal as living in agreement with nature was a conscious attempt to offer a non-circular account of what constitutes virtue (239). In the third section Striker works out the notion of the craft that the Stoics supposed virtue to be:

it is stochastic in the sense that the result of the technical performance depends in part upon external factors not controlled by the craft. Therefore, individual performances are not to be judged by their success, but by their correctness. … its primary goal is not identical with the result pursued through the exercise of the craft. Though every step will be referrable to the intended result, that result is not the ultimate end for the sake of which the activity is performed. The ultimate aim of virtuous action lies in the correct performance itself as being our way of living in agreement with nature. (246)

Another discussion of natural law theory occupies the fourth section of this chapter. In discussing the case described by Cicero ( De off. III 90) in which two men, after a shipwreck, are left with a plank that will carry only one of them, Striker writes, “The point of the argument, which is not fully stated in the text, should be that if the Stoics admit, as they apparently must, that self-love is naturally stronger than benevolence towards a total stranger, then they will have to admit that it is natural, and hence appropriate, to save one’s life at the expense of another’s. But this is clearly not what one would expect from a virtuous person …” (257). This last claim is hardly obvious. At most one of the two men can survive, so it is impossible for the virtuous plank-hugger to benefit both himself and the stranger. Though Striker mentions Cicero’s solution, taken from Hecato, that “the man whose life is more valuable for himself or his country should be allowed to survive” (260), she does not connect this with the virtuous plank-hugger’s non-arbitrary decision to save himself instead of the presumably non-virtuous stranger. Thus it would only be if both plank-huggers were virtuous—a rare circumstance indeed!—that “the lot should decide” (260). In the fifth section Carneades’ moral theory and its influence on Antipater and on Antiochus of Ascalon are treated. The last section addresses the doctrine that the ‘governing part’ ( hegemonikon ) of the human soul is unitary reason, and that it is not only possible, but also natural and desirable, to be free from all emotions since they are due to a weakness of reason itself and go beyond or against right reason. Here Striker’s personal preference for an Aristotelian moral epistemology is undisguised. As I explain elsewhere ( Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy XIV, 1996), unlike Striker I do not find the manner in which the Stoic sage loves to be “disconcerting” (275). But she does not rest content with honoring the Peripatetic view that eudaimonia ultimately depends upon luck. She ends this chapter by imputing to the Stoics, without evidence or argument, a most uncharitable motivation: “they … misdescribed happiness in order to make it depend upon nothing but ourselves” (280). As Brad Inwood has suggested to me, Striker’s claim harks back to the now embarrassing Zellerian thesis about the essentially consolatory character of Hellenistic ethics. It is more plausible that the Stoics’ unusual ethical views are the result of painstaking, rigorous application of their arguments and theories coupled with the unapologetic adoption of a moral epistemology, inspired by Plato’s Socrates, which was unimpressed by popular (that is, Aristotelian) wisdom.

In Chapter Thirteen, “The role of oikeiosis in Stoic ethics”, Striker seeks to set out what the argument involving the doctrine of οἰκείωσις was, what it was meant to prove, how it was supposed to prove it, and whether it was successful. She notices that there are actually two distinct arguments containing an appeal to this concept of “coming to be (or being made to be) well-disposed towards something” (281). In the first argument, found in Cicero, De finibus III, oikeiosis is used to support the Stoic conception of the telos. In the second, which Striker sees as depending on the first, oikeiosis is said to be the foundation of justice. Striker rightly observes that “the Stoics tried to argue that happiness is not what the Peripatetics said it was” (285), and she endorses the Peripatetic conception of eudaimonia when, for example, she writes that “… Socrates would have been right in choosing death over wrongdoing simply because he would have been more miserable if he had chosen to do wrong—not because doing what he thought was morally right would make him happy. For happiness would seem to be impossible for him in either case” (296). From the Stoic perspective, however, since Socrates could justifiably take pride in choosing a righteous death over a disgraceful misdeed in the midst of circumstances he was not responsible for creating, this final moral victory effectively maintained his homologia and thus did, in fact, preserve his happiness. The concluding judgment of the chapter is that “justifying moral standards and finding out what human happiness consists in are different, though certainly not independent tasks” (297).

In Chapter Fourteen, “Antipater, or the art of living”, Striker contends that some of the arguments handed down to us from the second-century dispute about the Stoic definitions of the goal of life rely on “the improper use of identity statements, which … the Stoics, by their predilection for such propositions, seem practically to invite” (299). Yet Striker finds a serious dispute between Antipater and Carneades behind the superficial paradoxes that result from their web of sophistical tricks in attempting to define the human telos. I found her discussion of the important and infamous archer analogy in De finibus III 22 to be particularly helpful in understanding her analysis of the telos -formulae of Diogenes and Antipater. One criticism can be made of her treatment of stochastic crafts that are sports. She cites Epictetus’ Discourses 2.5.1-23 as the one passage where he compares the art of living to sports or games (315), yet she has overlooked 1.24.20, 1.25.7-8, 4.7.5, 4.7.19, and 4.7.29-31—five other passages in which Epictetus discusses this game analogy.

In her final chapter, Striker argues that the Stoics tried to construct a revised Socratic ethics that would be immune to Plato’s criticisms. She contends that the Stoics defended two Socratic theses that Plato abandoned in his “mature” dialogues: (a) virtue is sufficient for happiness; (b) virtue is a kind of knowledge or craft, namely, knowledge of good and evil. Striker cites Gorgias 471e as “probably the most explicit” statement of Socrates’ thesis that virtue (or justice) is all that is needed for happiness (317). She asserts that Socrates’ arguments in the Gorgias do not really support this thesis, but she provides no substantiation whatever for her assertion. Instead, she simply reports her (again Aristotelian) impression that “Socrates is overstating his case (and that Plato is aware of this—see the reactions of Callicles)” (318). To my mind, such impressionism dodges the task of the requisite philosophical justification.

The discussion then moves to Socrates’ argument in the Euthydemus 278e-282e and 289e-292e that the “kingly craft”, i.e. the knowledge of good and evil, i.e. virtue, is strictly speaking the only good because health, beauty, wealth, power and the like are only useful to those who know how to use them rightly. Striker’s treatment of this thesis in the Euthydemus is substantial, in contrast to her passing remark about it in the Gorgias. She teases out two different interpretations of the craft model, both of which she sees as consistent with it: that the ruling craft is sufficient for happiness (the Stoics’ position), and that it is merely necessary for happiness (Aristotle’s position). Striker thinks that Plato saw two problems arising from Socrates wanting to hold both that virtue (wisdom) is knowledge of good (and evil), and that the good that this knowledge produces is itself wisdom, and so not an object or product distinct from the knowledge or craft. She persuasively suggests that the Stoics followed Plato’s distinction in Philebus 65a between the good human life and goodness. This distinction provided the Stoics a means of solving the first problem. The sage, they explained, understands goodness as rational order and harmony, and the good human life as living in agreement with the order and harmony of nature, i.e. living rationally and virtuously. Just as the skill of a flautist can be distinguished from the performance of playing the flute, virtue is to be distinguished from the activity of living virtuously; happiness, strictly speaking, consists in living virtuously, not in virtue itself. To solve Plato’s second problem of defining the human good in terms of the good itself, Striker observes that the Stoics needed to define what the goodness of a human life consists in. They “notoriously” defined it as “the rational order and harmony displayed most conspicuously by the order of the universe” (324).

These influential essays are excellent scholarly contributions to our understanding of the history of Hellenistic philosophy. Having all of them in one volume will definitely be useful to specialists in ancient philosophy, though a number of the essays—especially several on epistemology—are likely to be rough going for the non-specialist. The inclusion of a name index and an index of passages cited is helpful, but the absence of a bibliography is unfortunate. Proofreading errors resulted in inconsistent spelling of “Sceptic”/”Skeptic” in Chapters One, Four, Six, Seven, and Nine, as well as in an entire passage on page 206 being left transliterated instead of being printed in Greek. What is more disappointing to this reviewer than these minor infelicities, however, is that Striker has not yet embarked on the more ambitious project of writing a continuous, integrated, comprehensive study of Hellenistic ethics and its Socratic, sophistic, Platonic, and Aristotelian antecedents. Such a book would merit even greater celebration than this handy volume.

IMAGES

  1. Year 11 Essay

    06.09 practice essay nine

  2. NOTICE WRITING SOLVED EXAMPLE class 11 and 12 th

    06.09 practice essay nine

  3. BE CURIOUS: Resources for A LEVEL AQA Literature.: YEAR 12 LESSON

    06.09 practice essay nine

  4. Lauren Ascough

    06.09 practice essay nine

  5. Tips for Writing an Essay 9 2 2 2 2 .pdf

    06.09 practice essay nine

  6. A sample Band 9 essay. Ielts Writing Academic, Writing Test, Essay

    06.09 practice essay nine

VIDEO

  1. First semester activity sheet 9th practice question paper

  2. Essay on childhood

  3. CLASS

  4. A Level English Language (9093) Paper 4- Section B: Language and the Self (Part 2)

  5. English new book class 6, unit 9, Lesson 9.6 page 72-74(Politeness)

  6. A Stitch in time saves nine|| The king's messenger STORY

COMMENTS

  1. 06.09 Practice Essay 9

    06 Practice Essay 9. In Henry James' novel e Portrait of a Lady, the character of Isabel Archer is given a git that serves as both an advantage and a problem in her life. Isabel is a young, independent, and spirited American woman who has been gited with intelligence, charm, and beauty. ese qualities allow her to navigate the social ...

  2. 06.09 Practice Essay Nine.docx

    Susan Prigozen 9 May 2021 Mrs. Sayre AP Literature 06.09 Practice Essay Nine The novel where the character has a gift is The Picture of Dorian Gray.Doran Gray is an ideal in the beginning of the novel. He is the archetype of beauty and youth, so much so that he captures the full attention of Basil Hallward and Lord Henry Wotton. Dorian's gift also comes with an ugly reverse side in the fact ...

  3. 06.09 Practice Essay Nine.pdf

    View 06.09 Practice Essay Nine.pdf from AP ENG LIT 234 at Weir High School, Weirton. AP Literature 5/11/22 Practice Essay Nine In Frankenstein by Mary Shelley, we are introduced to Victor

  4. AP English Literature and Composition Syllabus (FLP v20).docx

    06.06 Practice Essay Eight. 06.07 Love Song or Not. 06.08 More Than One Way: Discussion-Based Assessment. 06.09 Practice Essay Nine. Module 07: Discovery. 07.00 Discovery: Checklist. 07.01 Awakening as Discovery. 07.02 Discovery Through Strategy. 07.03 Practice Essay Ten. 07.04 Multiple Choice: Putting It All Together. 07.05 Natural Discoveries

  5. 06.09 Practice Essay 9 1 .pdf

    Practice Essay 9 Grace Smith 4/1/21 Hero's always have the weight of the world on their shoulders. It's a fact, the protagonist of the story has to defeat the bad guy, save the world, etc. One of the most iconic hero beats villain stories is Beowulf by anonymous; the tale of a murderous beast and the hero who beats it. This time, however, Beowulf pays the ultimate price.

  6. AP English Literature and Composition

    06.06 Practice Essay Eight; 06.07 Love Song or Not; 06.08 More Than One Way: Discussion-Based Assessment; 06.09 Practice Essay Nine; Module 07: Discovery. 07.00 Discovery: Checklist; 07.01 Awakening as Discovery; 07.02 Discovery Through Strategy; 07.03 Practice Essay Ten; 07.04 Multiple Choice: Putting It All Together; 07.05 Natural Discoveries

  7. PDF Course Syllabus

    07.04 AP Practice Essay Nine 07.05 Rhetoric in Action 07.06 AP Practice Essay Ten 07.07 Evaluate and Implement 07.08 AP Practice Essay Eleven 07.09 Crafting Sentence Variety 07.10 Memoir Journal 07.11 Contemporary Edition: Discussion-Based Assessment Student Edition

  8. 06.09 Module 6 Review and Discussion-Based Assessment ...

    3. Teens should be allowed to play dangerous sports. 4. Teens should not be allowed to play dangerous sports. What was the counterclaim? (This should be about the same topics as mentioned in card five. For example): 1. Volunteering should not become mandatory to graduate high school become it'll add more pressure to the students. 2.

  9. 06.09 Practice Essay Nine.docx

    Jor'Na Powell 06.09 Practice Essay Nine A greatly intelligent scientist called Victor Frankenstein, is a genius at creating life from death. It is soon that we discover his gift of creation is a curse of destruction. Frankenstein is a cautionary tale on the dangers of pursuing technology beyond mankind. Victor is a scientist hailing from Geneva, he studied at The University of Ingolstadt ...

  10. 07.08 Evaluate and Implement Literary Argument

    For this essay, I will use 06.09 Practice Essay Nine in response . to the prompt: Then wri te a well-developed essay analyzing th e . complex nature of the g ift and how the gift contrib utes to the . meaning of work as a w hole. 2. Review the prompt for the essay you have chosen to use .

  11. PDF AP Language and Composition Segment Two Pace Chart

    07.04 AP Practice Essay Nine 11-4/5-4/9 *9th Teacher Planning Day 07.05 Rhetoric in Action 07.06 AP Practice Essay Ten 07.07 Evaluate and Implement 12-4/12-4/16 07.08 AP Practice Essay Eleven 07.09 Crafting Sentence Variety 07.10 Memoir Journal 13-4/19-4/23 07.11 Contemporary Edition: Discussion-Based Assessment 08.00 Student Edition: Checklist

  12. 06.09. Flashcards

    Improve your grades and reach your goals with flashcards, practice tests and expert-written solutions today. Home. Subjects. Solutions. Search. Log in. Sign up. Password Needed! For "06.09." Password. Enter Password. About us. About Quizlet. Careers. Advertise with us. News. Get the app. For students. Flashcards. Learn ...

  13. AP English Language and Composition

    07.04 AP Practice Essay Nine; 07.05 Rhetoric in Action; 07.06 AP Practice Essay Ten; 07.07 Evaluate and Implement; 07.08 AP Practice Essay Eleven; 07.09 Crafting Sentence Variety; 07.10 Memoir Journal; 07.11 Contemporary Edition: Discussion-Based Assessment; Student Edition.

  14. Lauren Ascough

    06.09 Practice Essay Nine Lauren Ascough AP English Literature and Composition 19 th May 2022 Heather Roberts Literary work: Beowulf Author: Unknown The weight of the world is always on the shoulders of heroes. The protagonist of the story must indeed defeat the antagonist, save the world, and so on. Beowulf by anonymous, the story of a murderous beast and the hero who destroys it, is one of ...

  15. 06.09. Flashcards

    Quizlet has study tools to help you learn anything. Improve your grades and reach your goals with flashcards, practice tests and expert-written solutions today.

  16. 06.09 Practice Essay Nine.docx

    06.09 Practice Essay Nine To download this file, click: " File " → " Download As " → Choose your file format, & SAVE to your AP Lit folder that you have created. Respond to Question 3 on the 2018 AP Literature and Composition Exam.Use any work of literary merit to make your argument. Check out the Literary Argumentation Rubric Note: In order to prepare for the time constraints of ...

  17. 06.04 To Be or Not to Be

    Disposition Essay - CWV-101 ASSIGNMENT; Preview text. 06 To Be or Not to Be. ... 06.09 Practice Essay 9. AP English Literature & Composition None. More from: darkxsoci3ty 2. impact 2. Virtual Academy. Discover more. 5. 06.01 DNA and RNA Structure. AP Biology 100% (2) 5. 06.08 Biotechnology - assignment.

  18. 1997.6.9, Striker, Essays on Hellenistic Epistemology and Ethics

    This essay was Striker's contribution to the volume edited by S. Everson, Epistemology (Cambridge University Press, 1990). Her treatment of the criterion (or criteria) of truth in Epicurus, the Stoics, and the Sceptics here seems more of a shallow survey by comparison with the depth of analysis in other essays in this volume.

  19. 06.09 Practice Essay Nine done.docx

    06.09 Practice Essay Nine To download this file, click: " File " → " Download As " → Choose your file format, & SAVE to your AP Lit folder that you have created. Respond to Question 3 on the 2018 AP Literature and Composition Exam.Use any work of literary merit to make your argument. Check out the Literary Argumentation Rubric Note: In order to prepare for the time constraints of ...

  20. 05.08 Through a Child's Eyes

    06.09 Practice Essay 9. AP English Literature & Composition None. More from: darkxsoci3ty 1. impact 1. Virtual Academy. Discover more. 5. 06.08 Biotechnology - assignment. AP Biology 100% (1) 4. 01.09 Your Budget - assignment. Economics None. 2. 02.02 Factors of Production. Economics None. 3. 06.09 Practice Essay 9.

  21. 06.01 DNA and RNA Structure

    06.09 Practice Essay 9. AP English Literature & Composition None. 3. 06.04 To Be or Not to Be - assignment. AP English Literature & Composition None. 2. 05.04 How Do I Lead a Group Through a Difficult Conversation. business and leadership None. 2. 06.06 Practice Essay 8.